Tag Archives: probability

A Two-Sided Ontological Solution to the Sleeping Beauty Problem

Preprint published on the PhilSci archive.

I describe in this paper an ontological solution to the Sleeping Beauty problem. I begin with describing the hyper-entanglement urn experiment. I restate first the Sleeping Beauty problem from a wider perspective than the usual opposition between halfers and thirders. I also argue that the Sleeping Beauty experiment is best modelled with the hyper-entanglement urn. I draw then the consequences of considering that some balls in the hyper-entanglement urn have ontologically different properties from normal ones. In this context, drawing a red ball (a Monday-waking) leads to two different situations that are assigned each a different probability, depending on whether one considers “balls-as-colour” or “balls-as-object”. This leads to a two-sided account of the Sleeping Beauty problem.

This account supersides my previous preprints on this topic. Please do no cite previous work.


A Two-Sided Ontological Solution to the Sleeping Beauty Problem

1. The hyper-entanglement urn

Let us consider the following experiment. In front of you is an urn. The experimenter asks you to study very carefully the properties of the balls that are in the urn. You go up then to the urn and begin to examine its content carefully. You notice first that the urn contains only red or green balls. By curiosity, you decide to take a sample of a red ball in the urn. Surprisingly, you notice that while you pick up this red ball, another ball, but a green one, also moves simultaneously. You decide then to replace the red ball in the urn and you notice that immediately, the latter green ball also springs back in the urn. Intrigued, you decide then to catch this green ball. You notice then that the red ball also goes out of the urn at the same time. Furthermore, while you replace the green ball in the urn, the red ball also springs back at the same time at its initial position in the urn. You decide then to withdraw another red ball from the urn. But while it goes out of the urn, nothing else occurs. Taken aback, you decide then to undertake a systematic and rigorous study of all the balls in the urn.

At the end of several hours of a meticulous examination, you are now capable of describing precisely the properties of the balls present in the urn. The latter contains in total 1000 red balls and 500 green balls. Among the red balls, 500 are completely normal balls. But 500 other red balls have completely astonishing properties. Indeed, each of them is linked to a different green ball. When you remove one of these red balls, the green ball which is associated with it also goes out at the same time from the urn, as if it was linked to the red ball by a magnetic force. Indeed, if you remove the red ball from the urn, the linked green ball also disappears instantly. And conversely, if you withdraw from the urn one of the green balls, the red ball which is linked to it is immediately removed from the urn. You even try to destroy one of the balls of a linked pair of balls, and you notice that in such case, the ball of the other colour which is indissociably linked to it is also destroyed instantaneously. Indeed, it seems to you that relative to these pairs of balls, the red ball and the green ball which is linked to it behave as one single object.

The functioning of this urn leaves you somewhat perplexed. In particular, your are intrigued by the properties of the pairs of correlated balls. After reflection, you tell yourself that the properties of the pairs of correlated balls are finally in some respects identical to those of two entangled quantum objects. Entanglement (Aspect & al. 1982) is indeed the phenomenon which links up two quantum objects (for example, two photons), so that the quantum state of one of the entangled objects is correlated or anti-correlated with the quantum state of the other, whatever the distance where the latter is situated. As a consequence, each quantum object can not be fully described as an object per se, and a pair of entangled quantum objects is better conceived of as associated with a single, entangled state. It also occurs to you that perhaps a pair of correlated balls could be considered, alternatively, as a ubiquitous object, i.e. as an object characterised by its faculty of occupying two different locations at the same time, with the colours of its two occurrences being anti-correlated. Setting this issue aside for the moment, you prefer to retain the similarity with the more familiar quantum objects. You decide to call “hyper-entanglement urn” this urn with its astonishing properties. After reflection, what proves to be specific to this urn, is that it includes at the same time some normal and some hyper-entangled balls. The normal red balls are no different from our familiar balls. But hyper-entangled balls do behave in a completely different way. What is amazing, you think, is that nothing seemingly differentiates the normal red balls from the red hyper-entangled ones. You tell yourself finally that it could be confusing.

Your reflection on the pairs of hyper-entangled balls and their properties also leads you to question the way the balls which compose the pairs of hyper-entangled balls are to be counted. Are they to be counted as normal balls? Or do specific rules govern the way these pairs of hyper-entangled balls are to be counted? You add a normal red ball in a hyper-entanglement urn. It is then necessary to increment the number of red balls present in the urn. On the other hand, the total number of green balls is unaffected. But what when you add in the hyper-entanglement urn the red ball of a pair of hyper-entangled balls? In that case, the linked green ball of the same pair of hyper-entangled balls is also added instantly in the urn. Hence, when you add a red ball of a pair of hyper-entangled balls in the urn, it also occurs that you add at the same time its associated green ball. So, in that case, you must not only increment the total number of red balls, but also the total number of green balls present in the urn. In the same way, if you withdraw a normal red ball from the urn, you simply decrement the total number of red balls of the urn, and the number of green balls in the urn is unaffected. But if you remove the red ball (resp. green) of a pair of hyper-entangled balls, you must decrement the total number of red balls (resp. green) present in the urn as well as the total number of green balls (resp. red).

At this very moment, the experimenter happens again and withdraws all balls from the urn. He announces that you are going to participate in the following experiment:

The hyper-entanglement urn A fair coin will be randomly tossed. If the coin lands Heads, the experimenter will put in the urn a normal red ball. On the other hand, if the coin lands Tails, he will put in the urn a pair of hyper-entangled balls, composed of a red ball and a green ball, both indissociably linked. The experimenter also adds that the room will be put in absolute darkness, and that you will therefore be completely unable to detect the colour of the balls, no more that you will be able to know, when you will have withdrawn a ball from the urn, whether it is a normal ball, or a ball which is part of a pair of hyper-entangled balls. The experimenter tosses then the coin. While you catch a ball from the urn, the experimenter asks you to assess the likelihood that the coin felt Heads.

2. The Sleeping Beauty problem

Consider now the well-known Sleeping Beauty problem (Elga 2000, Lewis 2001). Sleeping Beauty learns that she will be put into sleep on Sunday by some researchers. A fair coin will be tossed and if the coin lands Heads, Beauty will be awakened once on Monday. On the other hand, if the coin lands Tails, Beauty will be awakened twice: on Monday and Tuesday. After each waking, she will be put into sleep again and will forget that waking. Furthermore, once awakened, Beauty will have no idea of whether it is Monday or Tuesday. On awakening on Monday, what should then be Beauty’s credence that the coin landed Heads?

At this step, one obvious first answer (I) goes as follows: since the coin is fair, the initial probability that the coin lands Head is 1/2. But during the course of the experiment, Sleeping Beauty does not get any novel information. Hence, the probability of Heads still remains 1/2.

By contrast, an alternative reasoning (II) runs as follows. Suppose the experiment is repeated many times, say, to fix ideas, 1000 times. Then there will be approximately 500 Heads-wakings on Monday, 500 Tails-wakings on Monday and 500 Tails-wakings on Tuesday. Hence, this reasoning goes, the probability of Heads equals 500/1500 = 1/3.

The argument for 1/2 and the argument for 1/3 yield conflicting conclusions. The Sleeping Beauty problem is usually presented accordingly as a problem arising from contradicting conclusions resulting from the two above-mentioned competing lines of reasoning aiming at assigning the probability of Heads once Beauty is awakened. I shall argue, however, that this statement of the Sleeping Beauty problem is somewhat restrictive and that we need to envisage the issue from a wider perspective. For present purposes, the Sleeping Beauty problem is the issue of calculating properly (i) the probability of Heads (resp. Tails) once Beauty is awakened; (ii) the probability of the day being Monday (resp. Tuesday) on awakening; and (iii) the probability of Heads (resp. Tails) on waking on Monday. From the halfer perspective, the probability of the day being Monday on awakening equals 3/4, and the probability of the day being Tuesday on awakening is 1/4. By contrast, from the thirder’s perspective, the probability of the day being Monday on awakening equals 2/3 and the probability of the day being Tuesday on awakening is 1/3.

But the argument for 1/2 and for 1/3 also have their own account of conditional probabilities. To begin with, the probability of Heads on waking on Tuesday is not a subject of disagreement, for it equals 0 in both accounts. The same goes for the probability of Tails on waking on Tuesday, since it equals 1 from the halfer’s or from the thirder’s viewpoint. But agreement stops when one considers the probability of Heads on waking on Monday. For it equals 2/3 from a halfer’s perspective. However, from a thirder’s perspective, it amounts to 1/2. On the other hand, the probability of Tails on waking on Monday is 1/3 from a halfer standpoint, and 1/2 for a thirder.

3. The urn analogy

In what follows, I shall present an ontological solution to the Sleeping Beauty problem, which rests basically on the hyper-entanglement urn experiment. A specific feature of this account is that it incorporates insights from the halfer and thirder standpoints, a line of resolution initiated by Nick Bostrom (2007) that has recently inspired some new contributions (Groisman 2008, Delabre 2008)1.

The argument for 1/3 and the argument for 1/2 rest basically on an urn analogy. This analogy is made explicit in the argument for 1/3 but is less transparent in the argument for 1/2. The argument for 1/3, to begin with, is based on an urn analogy which associates the situation related to the Sleeping Beauty experiment with an urn that contains, in the long run (assuming that the experiment is repeated, say, 1000 times), 500 red balls (Heads-wakings on Monday), 500 red balls (Tails-wakings on Monday) and 500 green balls (Tails-wakings on Tuesday), i.e. 1000 red balls and 500 green balls in total. In this context, the probability of Heads upon awakening is determined by the ratio of the number of Heads-wakings to the total number of wakings. Hence, P(Heads) = 500/1500 =1/3. The balls in the urn are normal ones and for present purposes, it is worth calling this sort of urn a “standard urn”.

On the other hand, the argument for 1/2 is also based on an urn analogy, albeit less transparently. The main halfer proponent grounds his reasoning on calculations (Lewis 2001), but for the sake of clarity, it is worth rendering the underlying associated analogy more apparent. For this purpose, let us recall how the calculation of the probability of drawing a red ball is handled by the argument for 1/2. If the coin lands Heads then the probability of drawing a red ball is 1, and if the coin lands Tails then this latter probability equals 1/2. We get then accordingly the probability of drawing a red ball (Monday-waking): P(R) = 1 x 1/2 + 1/2 x 1/2 = 3/4. By contrast, if the coin lands Tails, we calculate as follows the probability of drawing a green ball (Tuesday-waking): P(G) = 0 x 1/2 + 1/2 x 1/2 = 1/4. To sum up, according to the argument for 1/3: P(R) = 3/4 and P(G) = 1/4. For the sake of comparison, it is worth transposing this reasoning in terms of an urn analogy. Suppose then that the Sleeping Beauty experiment is iterated. It proves then that the argument for 1/2 is based on an analogy with a standard urn that contains 3/4 of red balls and 1/4 of green ones. These balls are also normal ones and the analogy underlying the argument for 1/2 is also with a “standard urn”. Now assuming as above that the experiment is repeated 1000 times, we get accordingly an urn that contains 500 red balls (Heads-wakings on Monday), 250 red balls (Tails-wakings on Monday) and 250 green balls (Tails-wakings on Tuesday), i.e. 750 red balls and 250 green balls in total. Such content of the urn results directly from Lewis’ calculation. However, as it stands, this analogy would arguably be a poor argument in favour of the halfer’s viewpoint. But at this step, we should pause and consider that Lewis’ argument for 1/2 did not rely on this urn analogy, though the latter is a consequence of Lewis’ calculation. We shall now turn to the issue of whether the standard urn is the correct analogy for the Sleeping Beauty experiment.

In effect, it turns out that the argument for 1/3 and the argument for 1/2 are based on an analogy with a standard urn. But at this stage, a question arises: is the analogy with the standard urn well-suited to the Sleeping Beauty experiment? In other terms, isn’t another urn model best suited? In the present context, this alternative can be formulated more accurately as follows: isn’t the situation inherent to the Sleeping Beauty experiment better put in analogy with the hyper-entanglement urn, rather than with the standard urn? I shall argue, however, that the analogy with the standard urn is mistaken, for it fails to incorporate an essential feature of the experiment, namely the fact that Monday-Tails wakings are indissociable from Tuesday-Tails wakings. For in the Tails case, Beauty cannot wake up on Monday without also waking up on Tuesday and reciprocally, she cannot wake up on Tuesday without also waking up on Monday.

When one reasons with the standard urn, one feels intuitively entitled to add red-Heads (Heads-wakings on Monday), red-Tails (Tails-wakings on Monday) and green-Tails (Tails-wakings on Tuesday) balls to compute frequencies. But red-Heads and red-Tails balls prove to be objects of an essentially different nature in the present context. In effect, red-Heads balls are in all respects similar to our familiar objects, and can be considered properly as single objects. By contrast, it turns out that red-Tails balls are quite indissociable from green-Tails balls. For we cannot draw a red-Tails ball without picking up the associated green-Tails ball. And conversely, we cannot draw a green-Tails ball without picking up the associated red-Tails ball. In this sense, red-Tails balls and the associated green-Tails balls do not behave as our familiar objects, but are much similar to entangled quantum objects. For Monday-Tails wakings are indissociable from Tuesday-Tails wakings. On Tails, Beauty cannot be awakened on Monday (resp. Tuesday) without being also awakened on Tuesday (resp. Monday). From this viewpoint, it is mistaken to consider red-Tails and green-Tails balls as separate objects. The correct intuition, I shall argue, is that the red-Tails and the associated green-Tails ball can be assimilated to a pair of hyper-entangled balls and constitute but one single object. In this context, red-Tails and green-Tails balls are best seen intuitively as constituents and mere parts of one single object. In other words, red-Heads balls and, on the other hand, red-Tails and green-Tails balls, cannot be considered as objects of the same type for probability purposes. And this situation justifies the fact that one is not entitled to add unrestrictedly red-Heads, red-Tails and green-Tails balls to compute probability frequencies. For in this case, one adds objects of intrinsically different types, i.e. one single object with the mere part of another single object.

Given what precedes, the correct analogy, I contend, is with a hyper-entanglement urn rather than with a normal urn. As will become clearer later, this new analogy incorporates the strengths of both above-mentioned analogies with the standard urn. And we shall now consider the Sleeping Beauty problem in light of this new perspective.

4. Consequences of the analogy with the hyper-entanglement urn

At this step, it is worth drawing the consequences of the analogy with the hyper-entanglement urn, that notably result from the ontological properties of the balls. Now the key point proves to be the following one. Recall that nothing seemingly distinguishes normal balls from hyper-entangled ones within the hyper-entanglement urn. And among the red balls, half are normal ones, but the other half is composed of red balls that are each hyper-entangled with a different green ball. If one considers the behaviour of the balls, it turns out that normal balls behave as usual. But hyper-entangled ones do behave differently, with regard to statistics. Suppose I add the red ball of a hyper-entangled pair into the hyper-entanglement urn. Then I also add instantly in the urn its associated green ball. Suppose, conversely, that I remove the red ball of a hyper-entangled pair from the urn. Then I also remove instantly its associated green ball.

At this step, we are led to the core issue of calculating properly the probability of drawing a red ball from the hyper-entanglement urn. Let us pause for a moment and forget temporarily the fact that, according to its classical formulation, the Sleeping Beauty problem arises from conflicting conclusions resulting from the argument for 1/3 and the argument for 1/2 on calculating the probability of Heads once Beauty is awakened. For as we did see it before, the problem also arises from the calculation of the probability of the day being Monday on awakening (drawing a red ball), since conflicting conclusions also result from the two competing lines of reasoning. In effect, Elga argues for 2/3 and Lewis for 3/4. Hence, the Sleeping Beauty problem could also have been formulated alternatively as follows: once awakened, what probability should Beauty assign to her waking on Monday? In the present context, this is tantamount to the probability of drawing a red ball from the hyper-entanglement urn.

What is then the response of the present account, based on the analogy with the hyper-entanglement urn, to the issue of calculating the probability of drawing a red ball? In the present context, “drawing a red ball” turns out to be somewhat ambiguous. For according to the ontological properties of the balls within the hyper-entanglement urn, one can consider red balls either from the viewpoint of colour-ness, or from the standpoint of object-ness2. Hence, in the present context, “drawing a red ball” can be interpreted in two different ways: either (i) “drawing a red ball-as-colour”; or (ii) “drawing a red ball-as-object”. Now disambiguating the notion of drawing a red ball, we should distinguish accordingly between two different questions. First, (i) what is the probability of drawing a red ball-as-colour (Monday-waking-as-time-segment)? Let us denote by P(R↑) the latter probability. Second, (ii) what is the probability of drawing a red ball-as-object (Monday-waking-as-object)? Let us denote it by P(R→). This distinction makes sense in the present context, since it results from the properties of the hyper-entangled balls. In particular, this richer semantics results from the case where one draws a green ball of a hyper-entangled pair from the urn. For in the latter case, this green ball is not a red one, but it occurs that one also picks up a red ball, since the associated red ball is withdrawn simultaneously.

Suppose, on the one hand, that we focus on the colour of the balls, and that we consider the probability P(R↑) of drawing a red ball-as-colour. It occurs now that there are 2/3 of red balls-as-colour and 1/3 of green balls-as-colour in the urn. Accordingly, the probability P(R↑) of drawing a red ball-as-colour equals 2/3. On the other hand, the probability P(G↑) of drawing a green ball-as-colour equals 1/3.

Assume, on the other hand, that we focus on balls as objects, considering that one pair of hyper-entangled balls behaves as one single object. Now we are concerned with the probability P(R→) of drawing a red ball-as-object. On Heads, the probability of drawing a red ball-as-object is 1. On Tails, we can either draw the red or the green ball of a hyper-entangled pair. But it should be pointed out that if we draw on Tails the green ball of a hyper-entangled pair, we also pick up instantly the associated red ball. Hence, the probability of drawing a red ball on Tails is also 1. Thus, P(R→) = 1 x 1/2 + 1 x 1/2 = 1. Conversely, what is the probability P(G→) of drawing a green ball-as-object (a waking on Tuesday)? The probability of drawing a green ball-as-object is 0 in the Heads case, and 1 in the Tails case. For in the latter case, we either draw the green or the red ball of a hyper-entangled pair. But even if we draw the red ball of the hyper-entangled pair, we draw then instantly its associated green ball. Hence, P(G→) = 0 x 1/2 + 1 x 1/2 = 1/2. To sum up: P(R→) = 1 and P(G→) = 1/2. The probability of drawing a red ball-as-object (a waking on Monday) is then 1, and the probability of drawing a green ball-as-object (a waking on Tuesday) is 1/2. Now it turns out that P(R→) + P(G→) = 1 + 1/2 = 1.5. In the present account, this results from the fact that drawing a red ball-as-object and drawing a green ball-as-object from a hyper-entangled pair are not exclusive events for probability purposes. For we cannot draw the red-Tails (resp. green-Tails) ball without drawing the associated green-Tails (resp. red-Tails) ball.

To sum up now. It turns out that the probability P(R↑) of drawing a red ball-as-colour (Monday-waking-as-time-segment) equals 2/3. And the probability P(G↑) of drawing a green ball-as-colour (Tuesday-waking-as-time-segment) equals 1/3. On the other hand, the probability P(R→) of drawing a red ball-as-object (Monday-waking-as-object) equals 1; and the probability P(G→) of drawing a green ball-as-object (Tuesday-waking-as-object) equals 1/2.

At this step, we are led to the issue of calculating properly the number of balls present in the urn. Now we should distinguish, just as before, according to whether one considers balls-as-colour or balls-as-object. Suppose then that we focus on the colour of the balls. Then we have grounds to consider that there are in total 2/3 of red balls and 1/3 of green balls in the hyper-entanglement urn, i.e. 1000 red ones and 500 green ones. This conforms with the calculation that results from the thirder’s standpoint. Suppose, that we rather focus on balls as single objects. Things go then differently. For we can consider first that there are 1000 balls as objects in the urn, i.e. 500 (red) normal ones and 500 hyper-entangled ones. Now suppose that the 500 (red) normal balls are removed from the urn. Now there only remain hyper-entangled balls within the urn. Suppose then that we pick up one by one the remaining balls from the urn, by removing alternatively one red ball and one green ball from the urn. Now it turns out that we can draw 250 red ones and 250 green ones from the urn. For once we draw a red ball from the urn, its associated green ball is also withdrawn. And conversely, when we pick up a green ball from the urn, its associated red ball is also withdrawn. Hence, inasmuch as we consider balls as objects, there are in total 750 red ones and 250 green ones in the urn. At this step, it should be noticed that this corresponds accurately to the composition of the urn which is associated with Lewis’ halfer calculation. But this now makes sense, as far as the analogy with the hyper-entanglement urn is concerned. The above-mentioned analogy with the urn associated with Lewis’ halfer calculation was a poor argument inasmuch as the urn was a standard one, but things go differently when one considers now the analogy with the hyper-entanglement urn.

5. A two-sided account

From the above, it results that the line of reasoning which is associated with the balls-as-colour standpoint corresponds to the thirder’s reasoning. And conversely, the line of thought which is associated with the balls-as-object viewpoint echoes the halfer’s reasoning. Hence, the balls-as-colour/balls-as-object dichotomy parallels the thirder/halfer opposition. Grounded though they are on an unsuited analogy with the standard urn, the argument for 1/3 and the argument for 1/2 do have, however, their own strengths. In particular, the analogy with the urn in the argument for 1/3 does justice to the fact that the Sleeping Beauty experiment entails that 2/3 of Monday-wakings will occur in the long run. On the other hand, the analogy with the urn in the argument for 1/2 handles adequately the fact that one Heads-waking is put on a par with two Tails-wakings. In the present context however, these two analogies turn out to be one-sided and fail to handle adequately the probability notion of drawing a red ball (waking on Monday). But in the present context, the probability P(R↑) of drawing a red ball-as-colour corresponds to the thirder’s insight. And the probability P(R→) of drawing a red ball-as-object corresponds to the halfer’s line of thought. At this step, it turns out that the present account is two-sided, since it incorporates insights from the argument for 1/3 and from the argument for 1/2.

Finally, it turns out that the standard urn which is classically used to model the Sleeping Beauty problem does not allow for two possible interpretations of the probability of drawing a red ball. Rather, in the standard urn model, the two interpretations are exclusive of one another and this yields the classical contradiction between the argument for 1/3 and the argument for 1/2. But as we did see it, with the hyper-entanglement urn model, this contradiction dissolves, since two different interpretations of the probability of drawing a red ball (waking on Monday) are now allowed, yielding then two different calculations. In the latter model, these probabilities are no more exclusive of one another and the contradiction dissolves into complementarity.

Now the same ambiguity plagues the statement of the Sleeping Beauty problem, and its inherent notion of “waking”. For shall we consider “wakings-as-time-segment” or “wakings-as-object”? The initial statement of the Sleeping Beauty problem is ambiguous about that, thus allowing the two competing viewpoints to develop, with their respective associated calculations. But once we diagnose accurately the source of the ambiguity, namely the ontological status of the wakings, we allow for the two competing lines of reasoning to develop in parallel, thus dissolving the initial contradiction3.

In addition, what precedes casts new light on the argument for 1/3 and the argument for 1/2. For given that the Sleeping Beauty experiment, is modelled with a standard urn, both accounts lack the ability to express the difference between the probability P(R↑) of drawing a red ball-as-colour (a Monday-waking-as-time-segment) and the probability P(R→) of drawing a red ball-as-object (a Monday-waking-as-object), for it does not make sense with the standard urn. Consequently, there is a failure to express this difference with the standard urn analogy, when considering drawing a red ball. But such distinction makes sense with the analogy with the hyper-entanglement urn. For in the resulting richer ontology, the distinction between P(R↑) and P(R→) yields two different results: P(R↑) = 2/3 and P(R→) = 1.

At this step, it is worth considering in more depth the balls-as-colour/balls-as-object opposition, that parallels the thirder/halfer contradiction. It should be pointed out that “drawing a red ball-as-colour” is associated with an indexical (“this ball is red”), somewhat internal standpoint, that corresponds to the thirder’s insight. Typically, the thirder’s viewpoint considers things from the inside, grounding the calculation on the indexicality of Beauty’s present waking. On the other hand, “drawing a red ball-as-object” can be associated with a non-indexical (“the ball is red”), external viewpoint. This corresponds to the halfer’s standpoint, which can be viewed as more general and external.

As we did see it, the calculation of the probability of drawing a red ball (waking on Monday) is the core issue in the Sleeping Beauty problem. But what is now the response of the present account on conditional probabilities and on the probability of Heads upon awakening? Let us begin with the conditional probability of Heads on a Monday-waking. Recall first how the calculation goes on the two concurrent lines of reasoning. To begin with, the probability P(Heads|G) of Heads on drawing a green ball is not a subject of disagreement for halfers and thirders, since it equals 0 on both accounts. The same goes for the probability P(Tails|G) of Tails on drawing a green ball, since it equals 1 from the halfer’s or the thirder’s viewpoint. But agreement stops when one considers the probability P(Heads|R) of Heads on drawing a red ball. For P(Heads|R) = 1/2 from the thirder’s perspective and P(Heads|R) = 2/3 from the halfer’s viewpoint. On the other hand, the probability P(Tails|R) of Tails on drawing a red ball is 1/2 for a thirder and 1/3 for a halfer.

Now the response of the present account to the calculation of the conditional probability of Heads on drawing a red ball (waking on Monday) parallels the answer made to the issue of determining the probability of drawing a red ball. In the present account, P(Heads|G) = 0 and P(Tails|G) = 1, as usual. But we need to disambiguate how we interpret “drawing a red ball” by distinguishing between P(Heads|R↑) and P(Heads|R→), to go any further. For P(Heads|R↑) is the probability of Heads on drawing a red ball-as-colour. And P(Heads|R→) is the probability of Heads on drawing a red ball-as-object. P(Heads|R↑) is calculated in the same way as in the thirder’s account. Now we get accordingly: P(Heads|R↑) = 1/2. On the other hand, P(Heads|R→) is computed in the same way as from the halfer’s perspective, and we get accordingly: P(Heads|R→) = [P(Heads) x P(R→|Heads)] / P(R→) = [1/2 x 1] / 1 = 1/2.

Now the same goes for the probability of Heads upon awakening. For there are two different responses in the present account, depending on whether one considers P(R↑) or P(R→). If one considers balls-as-colour, the probability of Heads upon awakening is calculated in the same way as in the argument for 1/3, and we get accordingly: P(Heads↑) = 1/3 and P(Tails↑) = 2/3. On the other hand, if one is concerned with balls-as-object, it ensues, in the same way as with the halfer’s account, that there is no shift in the prior probability of Heads. As Lewis puts it, Beauty’s awakening does not add any novel information. It follows accordingly that the probability P(Heads→) of Heads (resp. Tails) on awakening still remains 1/2.

Finally, the above results are summarised in the following table:

halferthirderpresent account
P(Heads↑)1/31/3
P(Tails↑)2/32/3
P(Heads→)1/21/2
P(Tails→)1/21/2
P(drawing a red ball-as-colour) ≡ P(R↑)2/32/3
P(drawing a green ball-as-colour) ≡ P(G↑)1/31/3
P(drawing a red ball-as-object) ≡ P(R→)3/41
P(drawing a green ball-as-object) ≡ P(G→)1/41/2
P(Heads| drawing a red ball-as-colour) ≡ P(Heads|R↑)1/21/2
P(Tails| drawing a red ball-as-colour) ≡ P(Tails|R↑)1/21/2
P(Heads| drawing a red ball-as-object) ≡ P(Heads|R→)2/31/2
P(Tails| drawing a red ball-as-object) ≡ P(Tails|R→)1/31/2

At this step, it is worth recalling the diagnosis of the Sleeping Beauty problem put forth by Berry Groisman (2008). Groisman attributes the two conflicting responses to the probability of Heads to an ambiguity in the protocol of the Sleeping Beauty experiment. He argues that the argument for 1/2 is an adequate response to the probability of Heads on awakening, under the setup of coin tossing. On the other hand, he considers that the argument for 1/3 is an accurate answer to the latter probability, under the setup of picking up a ball from the urn. Groisman also considers that putting a ball in the box and picking up a ball out from the box are two different events, that lead therefore to two different probabilities. Roughly speaking, Groisman’s “coin tossing/picking up a ball” distinction parallels the present balls-as-colour/balls-as-object dichotomy. However, in the present account, putting a ball in the urn is no different from picking up a ball from the urn. For if we put in the urn a red ball of a hyper-entangled pair, we also immediately put in the urn its associated green ball. Rather, from the present standpoint, drawing (resp. putting in the urn) a red ball-as-colour from the urn is probabilistically different from picking up a red ball-as-object. The present account and Groisman’s analysis share the same overall direction, although the details of our motivations are significantly different.

Finally, the lesson of the Sleeping Beauty Problem proves to be the following: our current and familiar objects or concepts such as balls, wakings, etc. should not be considered as the sole relevant classes of objects for probability purposes. We should bear in mind that according to an unformalised axiom of probability theory, a given situation is classically modelled with the help of urns, dices, balls, etc. But the rules that allow for these simplifications lack an explicit formulation. However in certain situations, in order to reason properly, it is also necessary to take into account somewhat unfamiliar objects whose constituents are pairs of indissociable balls or of mutually inseparable wakings, etc. This lesson was anticipated by Nelson Goodman, who pointed out in Ways of Worldmaking that some objects which are prima facie completely different from our familiar objects also deserve consideration: “we do not welcome molecules or concreta as elements of our everyday world, or combine tomatoes and triangles and typewriters and tyrants and tornadoes into a single kind”.4 As we did see it, in some cases, we cannot add unrestrictedly an object of the Heads-world with an object of the Tails-world. For despite the appearances, objects of the Heads-world may have ontologically different properties from objects of the Tails-world. And the status of our probabilistic paradigm object, namely a ball, proves to be world-relative, since it can be a whole in the Heads-world and a part in the Tails-world. Once this goodmanian step accomplished, we should be less vulnerable to certain subtle cognitive traps in probabilistic reasoning.

Acknowledgements

I thank Jean-Paul Delahaye and Claude Panaccio for useful discussion on earlier drafts. Special thanks are due to Laurent Delabre for stimulating correspondence and insightful comments.

References

Arntzenius, F. (2002). Reflections on Sleeping Beauty. Analysis, 62-1, 53-62

Aspect, A., Dalibard, J. & Roger, G. (1982). Physical Review Letters. 49, 1804-1807

Black, M. (1952). The Identity of Indiscernibles. Mind 61, 153-164

Bostrom, N. (2002). Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy. (New York: Routledge)

Bostrom, N. (2007). Sleeping Beauty and Self-Location: A Hybrid Model. Synthese, 157, 59-78

Bradley, D. (2003). Sleeping Beauty: a note on Dorr’s argument for 1/3. Analysis, 63, 266-268

Delabre, L. (2008). La Belle au bois dormant : débat autour d’un paradoxe. Manuscript

Elga, A. (2000). Self-locating Belief and the Sleeping Beauty Problem. Analysis, 60, 143-147

Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of Worldmaking. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company)

Groisman, B. (2008). The End of Sleeping Beauty’s Nightmare. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, 409-416

Leslie, J. (2001). Infinite Minds (Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press)

Lewis, D. (2001). Sleeping Beauty: Reply to Elga. Analysis, 61, 171-176

Monton, B. (2002). Sleeping Beauty and the Forgetful Bayesian. Analysis, 62, 47-53

White, R. (2006). The generalized Sleeping Beauty problem: A challenge for thirders. Analysis, 66, 114-119

1 Bostrom opens the path to a third way out to the Sleeping Beauty problem: “At any rate, one might hope that having a third contender for how Beauty should reason will help stimulate new ideas in the study of self-location”. In his account, Bostrom sides with the halfer on P(Heads) and with the thirder on conditional probabilities, but his treatment has some counter-intuitive consequences on conditional probabilities.

2 This issue relates to the identity of indiscernibles and is notably hinted at by Max Black (1952, p. 156) who describes a universe composed of two identical spheres: “Isn’t it logically possible that the universe should have contained nothing but two exactly similar spheres? We might suppose that each was made of chemically pure iron, had a diameter of one mile, that they had the same temperature, colour, and so on, and that nothing else existed. Then every quality and relational characteristic of the one would also be a property of the other.” In the present context, it should be pointed out that the colours of the hyper-entangled balls are anti-correlated. John Leslie (2001, p. 153) also raises a similar issue with his paradox of the balls: “Here is a yet greater paradox for Identity of Indiscernibles to swallow. Try to picture a cosmos consisting just of three qualitatively identical spheres in a straight line, the two outer ones precisely equidistant from the one at the centre. Aren’t there plain differences here? The central sphere must be nearer to the outer spheres than these are to each other. Identity of Indiscernibles shudders at the symmetry of the situation, however. It holds that the so-called two outer spheres must really be only a single sphere. And this single sphere, which now has all the same qualities as its sole surviving partner, must really be identical to it. There is actually just one sphere!”.

3 It is worth noting that the present treatment of the Sleeping Beauty problem, is capable of handling several variations of the original problem that have recently flourished in the literature. For the above solution to the Sleeping Beauty problem applies straightforwardly, I shall argue, to these variations of the original experiment. Let us consider, to begin with, a variation were on Heads, Sleeping Beauty is not awakened on Monday but instead on Tuesday. This is modelled with a hyper-entanglement urn that receives one normal green ball (instead of a red one in the original experiment) in the Heads case.

Let us suppose, second, that Sleeping Beauty is awakened two times on Monday in the Tails case (instead of being awakened on both Monday and Tuesday). This is then modelled with a hyper-entanglement urn that receives one pair of hyper-entangled balls which are composed of two red balls in the Tails case (instead of a pair of hyper-entangled balls composed of a red and a green ball in the original experiment).

Let us imagine, third, that Beauty is awakened two times – on Monday and Tuesday – in the Heads case, and three times – on Monday, Tuesday and Wednesday – in the Tails case. This is then modelled with a hyper-entanglement urn that receives one pair of hyper-entangled balls composed of one red ball and one green ball in the Heads case; and in the Tails case, the hyper-entanglement urn is filled with one triplet of hyper-entangled balls, composed of one red, one green and one blue ball.

4 Goodman (1978, p. 21).

A Third Route to the Doomsday Argument

A paper published (2009) in English in the Journal of Philosophical Research, vol. 34, pages 263-278 (with significant changes with regard to the preprint).

In this paper, I present a solution to the Doomsday argument based on a third type of solution, by contrast with, on the one hand, the Carter-Leslie view and on the other hand, the Eckhardt et al. analysis. I begin by strengthening both competing models by highlighting some variations of their ancestors models, which renders them less vulnerable to several objections. I describe then a third line of solution, which incorporates insights from both Leslie and Eckhardt’s models and fits more adequately with the human situation corresponding to the Doomsday argument. I argue then that the resulting two-sided analogy casts new light on the reference class problem. This leads finally to a novel formulation of the argument that could well be more consensual than the original one.

This paper is cited in:

  • Alasdair Richmond, The Doomsday Argument, Philosophical Books Vol. 47 No. 2 April 2006, pp. 129–142
  • Robert Northcott, A Dilemma for the Doomsday Argument, Ratio, Volume29-3, September 2016, pages 268-282
  • William Poundstone, How to Predict Everything: The Formula Transforming What We Know About Life and the Universe, 2019, Oneworld

A Third Route to the Doomsday Argument

In what follows, I will endeavor to present a solution to the problem arising from the Doomsday argument (DA). The solution thus described constitutes a third way out, compared to, on the one hand, the approach of the promoters of DA (Leslie 1993 and 1996) and on the other hand, the solution recommended by its detractors (Eckhardt 1993 and 1997, Sowers 2002).i

I. The Doomsday Argument and the Carter-Leslie model

For the sake of the present discussion, it is worth beginning with a brief presentation of DA. This argument can be described as reasoning which leads to a Bayesian shift, starting from an analogy between what was has been called the two-urn caseii and the corresponding human situation.

Let us consider first the two-urn case experiment (adapted from Bostrom 1997):

The two-urn case experiment An opaque urniii is in front of you. You know that it contains either 10 or 1000 numbered balls. A fair coin has been tossed at time T0 and if the coin landed tails, then 10 balls were placed in the urn; on the other hand, if the coin landed heads, 1000 balls were placed in the urn. The balls are numbered 1,2,3,…. You formulate then the assumptions Hfew (the urn contains only 10 balls) and Hmany (the urn contains 1000 balls) with the initial probabilities P (Hfew) = P (Hmany) = 1/2.

Informed of all the preceding, you randomly draw a ball at time T1 from the urn. You get then the ball #5. You endeavor to estimate the number of balls that were contained at T0 in the urn. You conclude then to an upward Bayesian shift in favor of the Hfew hypothesis.

The two-urn case experiment is an uncontroversial application of Bayes’ theorem. It is based on the two following concurrent assumptions:

(H1few)the urn contains 10 balls
(H2many)the urn contains 1000 balls

and the corresponding initial probabilities: P (H1) = P (H2) = 1/2. By taking into account the fact that E denotes the evidence according to which the randomly drawn ball carries the #5 and that P (E|H1) = 1/10 and P (E|H2) = 1/1000, an upward Bayesian shift follows, by a straightforward application of Bayes’ theorem. Consequently, the posterior probabilities are such that P'(H1) = 0.99 and P'(H2) = 0.01.

Let us consider, on the second hand, the human situation corresponding to DA. While being interested in the total number of humans that humankind will finally count, it is worth considering the two following concurrent hypotheses:

(H3few)the total number of humans having ever lived will amount to 1011 (Apocalypse near)
(H4many)the total number of humans having ever lived will amount to 1014 (Apocalypse far)

It appears now that every human being has his own birth rank, and that yours, for example, is about 60×109. Let us also assume, for the sake of simplicity, that the initial probabilities are such as P(H3) = P(H4) = 1/2. Now, according to Carter and Leslie, the human situation corresponding to DA is analogous to the two urn case.iv If we denote by E the fact that our birth rank is 60×109, an application of Bayes’ theorem, by taking into account the fact that P(E|H3) = 1/1011 and that P(E|H4) = 1/1014, leads to an important Bayesian shift in favor of the hypothesis of a near Apocalypse, i.e., P'(H3) = 0.999. The importance of the Bayesian shift which results from this reasoning, associated with a very worrying situation related to the future of humankind, from the only recognition of our birth rank, appears counter-intuitive. This intrinsic problem requires that we set out to find it a solution.

In such context, it appears that a solution to DA has to present the following characteristics. On the one hand, it must point out in which ways the human situation corresponding to DA is similar to the two-urn case or possibly, to an alternative model, the characteristics of which are to be specified. On the second hand, such solution to DA must point out in which ways one or several models on analogy with the human situation corresponding to DA are associated with a frightening situation for the future of humankind.

In what follows, I will endeavor to present a solution to DA. In order to develop it, it will be necessary first to build up the space of solutions for DA. Such a construction is a non-trivial task that requires the consideration of not only several objections that have been raised against DA, but also the reference class problem. Within this space of solutions, the solutions advocated by the supporters as well as critics of DA, will naturally be placed. I will finally show that within the space of solutions thus established, there is room for a third way out, which is in essence a different solution from that offered by the proponents and opponents of DA.

II. Failure of an alternative model based on the incremental objection of Eckhardt et al.

DA is based on the matching of a probabilistic model – the two-urn case – with the human situation corresponding to DA. In order to build the space of solutions for DA, it is necessary to focus on the models that constitute an alternative to the two-urn case, which can also be put in correspondence with the human situation corresponding to DA. Several alternative models have been described by the opponents to DA. However, for reasons that will become clearer later, not all these models can be accepted as valid alternative models to the two-urn case, and take a place within the space of solutions for DA. It is therefore necessary to distinguish among these models proposed by the detractors of DA, between those which are not genuine alternative models, and those which can legitimately be included within the space of solutions for DA.

A certain number of objections to DA were formulated first by William Eckhardt (1993, 1997). For the sake of the present discussion, it is worth distinguishing between two objections, among those which were raised by Eckhardt, and that I will call respectively: the incremental objection and the diachronic objection. With each one of these two objections is associated an experiment intended to constitute an alternative model to the two-urn case.

Let us begin with the incremental objection mentioned in Eckhardt (1993, 1997) and the alternative model associated with it. Recently, George Sowers (2002) and Elliott Sober (2003) have echoed this objection. According to this objection, the analogy with the urn that is at the root of DA, is ungrounded. Indeed, in the two-urn case experiment, the number of the balls is randomly chosen. However, these authors emphasize, in the case of the human situation corresponding to DA, our birth rank is not chosen at random, but is indeed indexed on the corresponding time position. Therefore, Eckhardt stresses, the analogy with the two-urn case is unfounded and the whole reasoning is invalidated. Sober (2003) develops a similar argument,v by stressing that no mechanism designed to randomly assign a time position to human beings, can be highlighted. Finally, such an objection was recently revived by Sowers. The latter focused on the fact that the birth rank of every human being is not random because it is indexed to the corresponding time position.

According to the viewpoint developed by Eckhardt et al., the human situation corresponding to DA is not analogous to the two-urn case experiment, but rather to an alternative model, which may be called the consecutive token dispenser. The consecutive token dispenser is a device, originally described by Eckhardtvi, that ejects consecutively numbered balls at regular intervals: “(…) suppose on each trial the consecutive token dispenser expels either 50 (early doom) or 100 (late doom) consecutively numbered tokens at the rate of one per minute”. A similar device – call it the numbered balls dispenser – is also mentioned by Sowers, where the balls are ejected from the urn and numbered in the order of their ejection, at the regular interval of one per minute:vii

There are two urns populated with balls as before, but now the balls are not numbered. Suppose you obtain your sample with the following procedure. You are equipped with a stopwatch and a marker. You first choose one of the urns as your subject. It doesn’t matter which urn is chosen. You start the stopwatch. Each minute you reach into the urn and withdraw a ball. The first ball withdrawn you mark with the number one and set aside. The second ball you mark with the number two. In general, the nth ball withdrawn you mark with the number n. After an arbitrary amount of time has elapsed, you stop the watch and the experiment. In parallel with the original scenario, suppose the last ball withdrawn is marked with a seven. Will there be a probability shift? An examination of the relative likelihoods reveals no.

Thus, under the terms of the viewpoint defended by Eckhardt et al., the human situation corresponding to DA is not analogous with the two-urn case experiment, but with the numbered balls dispenser. And this last model leads us to leave the initial probabilities unchanged.

The incremental objection of Eckhardt et al. is based on a disanalogy. Indeed, the human situation corresponding to DA presents a temporal nature, for the birth ranks are successively attributed to human beings depending on the time position corresponding to their appearance on Earth. Thus, the corresponding situation takes place, for example, from T1 to Tn, where 1 and n are respectively the birth ranks of the first and of the last humans. However, the two-urn case experiment appears atemporal, because when the ball is drawn at random, all the balls are already present within the urn. The two-urn case experiment takes place at a given time T0. It appears thus that the two-urn case experiment is an atemporal model, while the situation corresponding to DA is a temporal model. And this forbids, as Eckhardt et al. underscore, considering the situation corresponding to DA and the two-urn case as isomorphic.viii

At this stage, it appears that the atemporal-temporal disanalogy is indeed a reality and it cannot be denied. However, this does not constitute an insurmountable obstacle for DA. As we shall see, it is possible indeed to put in analogy the human situation corresponding to DA, with a temporal variation of the two-urn case. This can be done by considering the following experiment, which can be termed the incremental two-urn case (formally, the two-urn case++):

The two-urn case++. An opaque urn in front of you. You know that it contains either 10 or 1000 numbered balls. A fair coin has been tossed at time T0 and if the coin landed tails, then the urn contains only 10 balls, while if the coin landed heads, then the urn contains the same 10 balls plus 990 extra balls, i.e. 1000 balls in total. The balls are numbered 1, 2, 3, …. You formulate then the Hfew (the box contains only 10 balls) and Hmany (the box contains 1000 balls) hypotheses with initial probabilities P(Hfew) = P(Hmany) = 1/2. At time T1, a device will draw a ball at random, and will eject then every second a numbered ball in increasing order, from the ball #1 until the number of the randomly drawn ball. At that very time, the device will stop.

You are informed of all the foregoing, and the device expels then the ball #1 at T1, the ball #2 at T2, the ball #3 at T3, the ball #4 at T4, and the ball #5 at T5. The device then stops. You wish to estimate the number of balls that were contained at T0 in the urn. You conclude then to an upward Bayesian shift in favor of the Hfew hypothesis.

As we can see, such a variation constitutes a mere adaptation of the original two-urn case, with the addition of an incremental mechanism for the expulsion of the balls. The novelty with this variationix is that the experience has now a temporal feature, because the random selection is made at T1 and the randomly drawn ball is finally ejected, for example at T5.

At this stage, it is also worth analyzing the consequences of the two-urn case++ for the analysis developed by Eckhardt et al. Indeed, in the two-urn case++, the number of each ball ejected from the device is indexed on the range of its expulsion. For example, I draw the ball #60000000000. But I also know that the previous ball was the ball #59999999999 and that the penultimate ball was the ball #59999999998, and so on. However, this does not prevent me from thinking in the same manner as in the original two-urn case and from concluding to a Bayesian shift in favor of the Hfew hypothesis. In this context, the two-urn case++ experiment leads to the following consequence: the fact of being indexed with regard to time does not mean that the number of the ball is not randomly chosen. This can now be confronted with the main thesis of the incremental objection raised by Eckhardt et al., i.e. that the birth rank of each human being is not randomly chosen, but is rather indexed on the corresponding time position. Sowers especially believes that the cause of DA is that the number corresponding to the birth rank is time-indexed.x But what the two-urn case++ experiment and the corresponding analogy demonstrates is that our birth rank can be time-indexed and nevertheless be determined randomly in the context of DA. For this reason, the numbered balls dispenser model proposed by Eckhardt and Sowers can not be considered as an alternative model to the two-urn case, within the space of solutions for DA.

III. Success of an alternative model grounded on William Eckhardt’s diachronic objection

William Eckhardt (1993, 1997) also describes another objection to DA, which we shall call, for the sake of the present discussion, the diachronic objection. This latter objection, as we shall see it, is based on an alternative model to the two-urn case, which is different from the one that corresponds to the incremental objection. Eckhardt highlights the fact that it is impossible to perform a random selection, when there exists many yet unborn individuals within the corresponding reference class: “How is it possible in the selection of a random rank to give the appropriate weight to unborn members of the population?” (1997, p. 256).

This second objection is potentially stronger than the incremental objection. In order to assess its scope accurately, it is worth translating now this objection in terms of a probabilistic model. It appears that the model associated with Eckhardt’s diachronic objection can be built from the two-urn case’s structure. The corresponding variation, which can be termed the diachronic two-urn case, goes as follows:

The diachronic two-urn case. An opaque urn in front of you. You know that it contains either 10 or 1000 numbered balls. A fair coin has been tossed at time T0. If the coin fell tails, 10 balls were then placed in the urn, while if the coin fell heads, 10 balls were also placed in the urn at time T0, but 990 supplementary balls will be also added to the urn at time T2, bringing up the total number of balls finally contained in the urn to 1000. The balls are numbered 1, 2, 3, …. You then formulate Hfew (the urn finally contains only 10 balls) and Hmany (the urn finally contains1000 balls) hypotheses with the initial probabilities P (Hfew) = P (Hmany) = 1 / 2.

Informed of all the above, you randomly draw at time T1 a ball from the urn. You get then the ball #5. You wish to estimate the number of balls that ultimately will be contained in the urn at T2. You conclude then that the initial probabilities remain unchanged.

At this stage, it appears that the protocol described above does justice to Eckhardt’s strong idea that it is impossible to perform a random selection where there are many yet unborn members in the reference class. In the diachronic two-urn case, the 990 balls, which are possibly (if the coin falls heads) added in T2 account for these members not yet born. In such a situation, it would be quite erroneous to conclude to a Bayesian shift in favor of the Hfew hypothesis. But what can be inferred rationally in such a case is that the prior probabilities remain unchanged.

We can also see that the structure of the protocol of the diachronic two-urn case is quite similar to the original two-urn case experiment (which we shall now term, by contrast, the synchronic two-urn case). This will allow now for making easy comparisons. So we see that if the coin lands tails: the situation is the same in both experiments, synchronic and diachronic. However, the situation is different if the coin lands heads: in the synchronic two-urn case, the 990 balls are already present in the urn at T0; on the other hand, in the model of the diachronic two-urn case, 990 extra balls are added to the urn later, namely at T2. As we can see, the diachronic two-urn case based on Eckhardt’s diachronic objection deserves completely to take a place within the space of solutions for DA.

IV. Construction of the preliminary space of solutions

In light of the foregoing, we are now in a position to appreciate how much the analogy underlying DA is appropriate. It appears indeed that two alternative models to model the analogy with the human situation corresponding to DA are in competition: on the one hand, the synchronic two-urn case advocated by the promoters of DA and, on the other hand, the diachronic two-urn case, based on Eckhardt’s diachronic objection. It turns out that these two models share a common structure, which allows for making comparisons.xi

At this step, the question that arises is the following: is the human situation corresponding to DA in analogy with (i) the synchronic two-urn case, or (ii) the diachronic two-urn case? In response, the next question follows: is there an objective criterion that allows one to choose, preferentially, between the two competing models? It appears not. Indeed, neither Leslie nor Eckhardt do provide objective reasons for justifying the choice of their favorite model, and for rejecting the alternative model. Leslie, first, defends the analogy of the human situation corresponding to DA with the lottery experiment (here, the synchronic two-urn case). At the same time, Leslie acknowledges that DA is considerably weakened if our universe is of an indeterministic nature, i.e. if the total number of people who will ever exist has not yet been settled.xii But it turns out that such indeterministic situation corresponds completely with the diachronic two-urn case. For the protocol of this experiment takes into account the fact that the total number of balls which will ultimately be contained in the urn, is not known at the time when the random drawing is performed. We see it finally, Leslie liberally accepts that the analogy with the synchronic two-urn case may not prevail in certain indeterministic circumstances, where, as we have seen, the diachronic two-urn case would apply.

Otherwise, a weakness in the position defended by Eckhardt is that he rejects the analogy with the lottery experiment (in our terminology, the synchronic two-urn case) in all cases. But how can we be certain that an analogy with the synchronic two-urn case does not prevail, at least for a given situation? It appears here that we lack the evidence allowing us to reject such an hypothesis with absolute certainty.

To sum now. Within the space of solutions for DA resulting from the foregoing, it follows now that two competing models may also be convenient to model the human situation corresponding to DA: Leslie’s synchronic two-urn case or Eckhardt’s diachronic two-urn case. At this stage, however, it appears that no objective criterion allows for preferring one or the other of these two models. In these circumstances, in the lack of objective evidence to make a choice between the two competing models, we are led to apply a principle of indifference, which leads us to retain both models as roughly equiprobable. We attribute then (Figure 1), applying a principle of indifference, a probability P of 1/2 to the analogy with the synchronic two-urn case (associated with a terrifying scenario), and an identical probability of 1/2 to the analogy with the diachronic two-urn case (associated with a reassuring scenario).

CaseModelT0T2PNature of the scenario
1synchronic two-urn case1/2terrifying
2diachronic two-urn case1/2reassuring

Figure 1.

However, it appears that such an approach is of a preliminary nature, for in order to assign a probability to each specific situation inherent in DA, it is necessary to take into account all the elements underlying DA. But it appears that a key element of DA has not yet been taken into account. It is the notoriously awkward reference class problem.

V. The reference class problem

Let us begin by recalling the reference class problem.xiii Basically, it is the problem of the correct definition of “humans”. More accurately, the problem can be stated as follows: how can the reference class be objectively defined in the context of DA? For a more or less extensive or restrictive definition of the reference class can be used. An extensively defined reference class would include, for example, the somewhat exotic varieties corresponding to a future evolution of humankind, with for example an average IQ equal to 200, a double brain or backward causation abilities. On the other hand, a restrictively defined reference class would only include those humans whose characteristics are exactly those of – for example – our subspecies Homo sapiens sapiens. Such a definition would exclude the extinct species such as Homo sapiens neandertalensis, as well as a possible future subspecies such as Homo sapiens supersapiens. To put this in line with our current taxonomy, the reference class can be set at different levels, which correspond to the Superhomo super-genus, the Homo genus, the Homo sapiens species, the Homo sapiens sapiens subspecies, etc. At this stage, it appears that we lack an objective criterion allowing to choose the corresponding level non-arbitrarily.

The solution to the reference class problem proposed by Leslie’s, which is exposed in the response made to Eckhardt (1993) and in The End of the World (1996), goes as follows: one can choose the reference class more or less as one wishes, i.e. at any level of extension or of restriction. Once this choice has been made, it suffices to adjust accordingly the initial probabilities, and DA works again. The only reservation mentioned by Leslie is that the reference class should not be chosen at an extreme level of extension or restriction.xiv According to Leslie, the fact that every human being can belong to different classes, depending on whether they are restrictively or extensively defined, is not a problem, because the argument works for each of those classes. In this case, says Leslie, a Bayesian shift follows for whatever class reference, chosen at a reasonable level of extension or of restriction. And Leslie illustrates this point of view by an analogy with a multi-color urn, unlike the one-color urn of the original two-urn case experiment. He considers an urn containing balls of different colors, for example red and green. A red ball is drawn at random from the urn. From a restrictive viewpoint, the ball is a red ball and then there is no difference with the two-urn case. But from a more extensive viewpoint, the ball is also a red-or-green ball.xv According to Leslie, although the initial probabilities are different in each case, a Bayesian shift results in both cases.xvi As we can see, the synchronic two-urn case can be easily adapted to restore the essence of Leslie’s multi-color model. It suffices in effect to replace the red balls of the original synchronic two-urn case with red-or-green balls. The resulting two-color model is then in all respects identical to the original synchronic two-urn case experiment, and leads to a Bayesian shift of the same nature.

At this stage, in order to incorporate properly the reference class problem into the space of solutions for DA, we still need to translate the diachronic two-urn case into a two-color variation.

A. The two-color diachronic two-urn case

In the one-color original experiment which corresponds to the diachronic two-urn case, the reference class is that of the red balls. It appears here that one can construct a two-color variation, which is best suited for handling the reference class problem, where the relevant class is that of red-or-green balls. The corresponding two-color variation is in all respects identical with the original diachronic two-urn case, the only difference being that the first 10 balls (#1 to #10) are red and the other 990 balls (#11 to #1000) are green. The corresponding variation runs as follows:

The two-color diachronic two-urn case. An opaque urn in front of you. You know it contains either 10 or 1000 numbered balls (consisting of 10 red balls and 990 green balls). The red balls are numbered #1, #2, …, #9, #10 and the green ones #11, #12, .., #999, #1000. A fair coin has been tossed at time T0. If the room fell tails, 10 balls were then placed in the urn, while if the coin fell heads, 10 red balls were also placed in the urn at time T0, but 990 green balls will be then added to the urn at time T2, bringing thus the total number of balls in the urn to 1000. You formulate then the hypotheses Hfew (the urn contains finally only 10 red-or-green balls) and Hmany (the box finally contains 1000 red-or-green balls) with the prior probabilities P(Hfew) = P(Hmany) = 1/2.

After being informed of all the above, you draw at time T1 a ball at random from the urn. You get the red ball #5. You proceed to estimate the number of red-or-green balls which will ultimately be contained in the urn at T2. You conclude that the initial probabilities remain unchanged.

As we can see, the structure of this two-color variation is in all respects similar to that of the one-color version of the diachronic two-urn case. In effect, we can considered here the class of red-or-green balls, instead of the original class of red balls. And in this type of situation, it is rational to conclude in the same manner as in the original one-color version of the diachronic two-urn case experiment that the prior probabilities remain unchanged.

B. Non-exclusivity of the synchronic one-color model and of the diachronic two-color model

With the help of the machinery at hand to tackle the reference class problem, we are now in a position to complete the construction of the space of solutions for DA, by incorporating the above elements. On a preliminary basis, we have assigned a probability of 1/2 to each of the one-color two-urn case – synchronic and diachronic – models, by associating them respectively with a terrifying and a reassuring scenario. But what is the situation now, with the presence of two-color models, which are better suited for handling the reference class problem?

Before evaluating the impact of the two-color model on the space of solutions for DA, it is worth defining first how to proceed in putting the two-color models and our present human situation into correspondence. For this, it suffices to assimilate the class of red balls to our current subspecies Homo sapiens sapiens and the class of red-or-green balls to our current species Homo sapiens. Similarly, we shall assimilate the class of green balls to the subspecies Homo sapiens supersapiens, a subspecies more advanced than our own, which is an evolutionary descendant of Homo sapiens sapiens. A situation of this type is very common in the evolutionary process that governs living species. Given these elements, we are now in a position to establish the relationship of the probabilistic models with our present situation.

At this stage it is worth pointing out an important property of the two-color diachronic model. It appears indeed that the latter model is susceptible of being combined with a one-color synchronic two-urn case. Suppose, then, that a one-color synchronic two-urn case prevails: 10 balls or 1000 red balls are placed in the urn at time T0. But this does not preclude green balls from being also added in the urn at time T2. It appears thus that the one-color synchronic model and the diachronic two-color model are not exclusive of one another. For in such a situation, a synchronic one-color two-urn case prevails for the restricted class of red balls, whereas a diachronic two-color model applies to the extended class of red-or-green balls. At this step, it appears that we are on a third route, of pluralistic essence. For the fact of matching the human situation corresponding to DA with the synchronic or the (exclusively) diachronic model, are well monist attitudes. In contrast, the recognition of the joint role played by both synchronic and diachronic models, is the expression of a pluralistic point of view. In these circumstances, it is necessary to analyze the impact on the space of solutions for DA of this property of non-exclusivity which has just been emphasized.

In light of the foregoing, it appears that four types of situations must now be distinguished, within the space of solutions for DA. Indeed, each of the two initial one-color models – synchronic and diachronic – can be associated with a two-color diachronic two-urn case. Let us begin with the case (1) where the synchronic one-color model applies. In this case, one should distinguish between two types of situations: either (1a) nothing happens at T2 and no green ball is added to the urn at T2, or (1b) 990 green balls are added in the urn at T2. In the first case (1a) where no green ball is added to the urn at T2, we have a rapid disappearance of the class of red balls. Similarly, we have a disappearance of the corresponding class of red-or-green balls, since it identifies itself here with the class of red balls. In such a case, the rapid extinction of Homo sapiens sapiens (the red balls) is not followed by the emergence of Homo sapiens supersapiens (the green balls). In such a case, we observe the rapid extinction of the sub-species Homo sapiens sapiens and the correlative extinction of the species Homo sapiens (the red-or-green balls). Such a scenario, admittedly, corresponds to a form of Doomsday that presents a very frightening nature.

Let us consider now the second case (1b), where we are always in the presence of a synchronic one-color model, but where now green balls are also added in the urn at T2. In this case, 990 green balls are added at T2 to the red balls originally placed in the urn at T0. We have then a rapid disappearance of the class of red balls, which accompanies, however, the survival of the class of red-or-green balls given the presence of green balls at T2. In this case (1b), one notices that a synchronic one-color model is combined with a diachronic two-color model. Both models prove to be compatible, and non-exclusive of one another. If we translate this in terms of the third route, one notices that, according to the pluralistic essence of the latter, the synchronic one-color model applies to the class, narrowly defined, of red balls, while a two-color diachronic model also applies to the class, broadly defined, of red-or-green balls. In this case (1b), the rapid extinction of Homo sapiens sapiens (the red balls) is followed by the emergence of the most advanced human subspecies Homo sapiens supersapiens (the green balls). In such a situation, the restricted class Homo sapiens sapiens goes extinct, while the more extended class Homo sapiens (red-or-green balls) survives. While the synchronic one-color model applies to the restricted class Homo sapiens sapiens, the diachronic two-color model prevails for the wider class Homo sapiens. But such an ambivalent feature has the effect of depriving the original argument of the terror which is initially associated with the one-color synchronic model. And finally, this has the effect of rendering DA innocuous, by depriving it of its originally associated terror. At the same time, this leaves room for the argument to apply to a given class reference, but without its frightening and counter-intuitive consequences .

As we can see, in case (1), the corresponding treatment of the reference class problem is different from that advocated by Leslie. For on Leslie’s view, the synchronic model applies irrespective of the chosen reference class. But the present analysis leads to a differential treatment of the reference class problem. In case (1a), the synchronic model prevails and a Bayesian shift applies, as well as in Leslie’s account, both to the class of red balls and to the class of red-or-green balls. But in case (1b), the situation goes differently. Because if a one-color synchronic model applies to the restricted reference class of red balls and leads to a Bayesian shift, it appears that a diachronic two-color model applies to the extended reference class of red-or-green balls, leaving the initial probability unchanged. In case (1b), as we can see, the third route leads to a pluralistic treatment of the reference class problem.

Let us consider now the second hypothesis (2) where the diachronic one-color model prevails. In this case, 10 red balls are placed in the urn at T0, and 990 other red balls are added to the urn at T2. Just as before, we are led to distinguish two situations. Either (2a) no green ball is added to the urn at T2, or (2b) 990 green balls are also added to the urn at T2. In the first case (2a), the diachronic one-color model applies. In such a situation (2a), no appearance of a much-evolved human subspecies such as Homo sapiens supersapiens occurs. But the scenario in this case is also very reassuring, since our current subspecies Homo sapiens sapiens survives. In the second case (2b), where 990 green balls are added to the urn at T2, a diachronic two-color model adds up to the initial diachronic one-color model. In such a case (2b), it follows the emergence of the most advanced subspecies Homo sapiens supersapiens. In this case, the scenario is doubly reassuring, since it leads both to the survival of Homo sapiens sapiens and of Homo sapiens supersapiens. As we can see, in case (2), it is the diachronic model which remains the basic model, leaving the prior probability unchanged.

At this step, we are in a position to complete the construction of the space of solutions for DA. Indeed, a new application of a principle of indifference leads us here to assign a probability of 1/4 to each of the 4 sub-cases: (1a), (1b), (2a), (2b). The latter are represented in the figure below:

CaseT0T2P
11a1/4
1b1/4
22a1/4
2b● ○1/4

Figure 2.

It suffices now to determine the nature of the scenario that is associated with each of the four sub-cases just described. As has been discussed above, a worrying scenario is associated with hypothesis (1a), while a reassuring scenario is associated with the hypotheses (1b), (2a) and (2b):

CaseT0T2PNature of the scenarioP
11a1/4terrifying1/4
1b1/4reassuring
22a1/4reassuring3/4
2b● ○1/4reassuring

Figure 3.

We see it finally, the foregoing considerations lead to a novel formulation of DA. For it follows from the foregoing that the original scope of DA should be reduced, in two different directions. It should be acknowledged, first, that either the one-color synchronic model or the diachronic one-color model applies to our current subspecies Homo sapiens sapiens. A principle of indifference leads us then to assign a probability of 1/2 to each of these two hypotheses. The result is a weakening of DA, as the Bayesian shift associated with a terrifying assumption no longer concerns but one scenario of the two possible scenarios. A second weakening of DA results from the pluralist treatment of the reference class problem. For in the case where the one-color synchronic model (1) applies to our subspecies Homo sapiens sapiens, two different situations must be distinguished. Only one of them, (1a) leads to the extinction of both Homo sapiens sapiens and Homo sapiens and corresponds thus to a frightening Doomsday. In contrast, the other situation (1b) leads to the demise of Homo sapiens sapiens, but to the correlative survival of the most advanced human subspecies Homo sapiens supersapiens, and constitutes then a quite reassuring scenario. At this stage, a second application of the principle of indifference leads us to assign a probability of 1/2 to each of these two sub-cases (see Figure 3). In total, a frightening scenario is henceforth associated with a probability of no more than 1/4, while a reassuring scenario is associated with a probability of 3/4.

As we can see, given these two sidesteps, a new formulation of DA ensues, which could prove to be more plausible than the original one. Indeed, the present formulation of DA can now be reconciled with our pretheoretical intuition. For the fact of taking into account DA now gives a probability of 3/4 for all reassuring scenarios and a probability of no more than 1/4 for a scenario associated with a frightening Doomsday. Of course, we have not completely eliminated the risk of a frightening Doomsday. And we must, at this stage, accept a certain risk, the scope of which appears however limited. But most importantly, it is no longer necessary now to give up our pretheoretical intuitions.

Finally, the preceding highlights a key facet of DA. For in a narrow sense, it is an argument related to the destiny of humankind. And in a broader sense (the one we have been concerned with so far) it emphasizes the difficulty of applying probabilistic models to everyday situations,xvii a difficulty which is often largely underestimated. This opens the path to a wide field which presents a real practical interest, consisting of a taxonomy of probabilistic models, the philosophical importance of which would have remained hidden without the strong and courageous defense of the Doomsday argument made by John Leslie.xviii

References

Bostrom, Nick. 1997. “Investigations into the Doomsday argument.” preprint.

———. 2002. Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy New York: Routledge.

Chambers, Timothy. 2001. “Do Doomsday’s Proponents Think We Were Born Yesterday?” Philosophy 76: 443-450.

Delahaye, Jean-Paul. 1996. “Recherche de modèles pour l’argument de l’apocalypse de Carter-Leslie.” manuscrit.

Eckhardt, William. 1993. “Probability Theory and the Doomsday Argument.” Mind 102: 483-488.

———. 1997. “A Shooting-Room view of Doomsday.” Journal of Philosophy 94: 244-259.

Franceschi, Paul. 1998. “Une solution pour l’argument de l’Apocalypse.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28: 227-246.

———. 1999. “Comment l’urne de Carter et Leslie se déverse dans celle de Hempel.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29: 139-156, English translation under the title “The Doomsday Argument and Hempel’s Problem” .

———. 2002. “Une application des n-univers à l’argument de l’Apocalypse et au paradoxe de Goodman.” Corté: University of Corsica, doctoral dissertation.

Hájek, Alan. 2002. “Interpretations of Probability.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2002/entries/probability-interpret.

Korb, Kevin. & Oliver, Jonathan. 1998. “A Refutation of the Doomsday Argument.” Mind 107: 403-410.

Leslie, John. 1993. “Doom and Probabilities.” Mind 102: 489-491.

———. 1996. The End of the World: the science and ethics of human extinction London: Routledge.

Sober, Eliott. 2003.An Empirical Critique of Two Versions of the Doomsday Argument – Gott’s Line and Leslie’s Wedge.” Synthese 135-3: 415-430.

Sowers, George. 2002. “The Demise of the Doomsday Argument.” Mind 111: 37-45.

i The present analysis of DA is an extension of Franceschi (2002).

ii Cf. Korb & Oliver (1998).

iii The original description by Bostrom of the two-urn case refers to two separate urns. For the sake of simplicity, we shall refer here equivalently to one single urn (which contains either 10 or 1000 balls).

iv More accurately, Leslie considers an analogy with a lottery experiment.

v Cf (2003: 9): “But who or what has the propensity to randomly assign me a temporal location in the duration of the human race? There is no such mechanism.” But Sober is mainly concerned with providing evidence with regard to the assumptions used in the original version of DA and with broadening the scope of the argument by determining the conditions of its application to real-life situations.

vi Cf. (1997: 251).

vii Cf. (2002: 39).

viii I borrow this terminology from Chambers (2001).

ix Other variations of the two-urn case++ can even be envisaged. In particular, variations of this experiment where the random process is performed diachronically and not synchronically (i.e. at time T0) can even be imagined.

x Cf. Sowers (2002: 40).

xi Both synchronic and diachronic two-urn case experiments can give rise to an incremental variation. The incremental variant of the (synchronic) two-urn case has been mentioned earlier: it consists of the two-urn case++. It is also possible to build a similar incremental variation of the diachronic two-urn case, where the ejection of the balls is made at regular time intervals. At this stage it appears that both models can give rise to such incremental variations. Thus, the fact of considering incremental variations of the two competing models – the synchronic two-urn case++ and the diachronic two-urn case++ – does not provide any novel elements with regard to the two original experiments. Similarly, we might consider some variations where the random sampling is done not at T0, but gradually, or some variants where a quantum coin is used, and so on. But in any case, such variations are susceptible to be adapted to each of the two models.

xii Leslie (1993: 490) evokes thus: “(…) the potentially much stronger objection that the number of names in the doomsday argument’s imaginary urn, the number of all humans who will ever have lived, has not yet been firmly settled because the world is indeterministic”.

xiii The reference class problem in probability theory is notably mentioned in Hájek (2002: s. 3.3). For a treatment of the reference class problem in the context of DA, see Eckhardt (1993, 1997), Bostrom (1997, 2002: ch. 4 pp. 69-72 & ch. 5), Franceschi (1998, 1999). The point emphasized in Franceschi (1999) can be construed as a treatment of the reference class problem within confirmation theory.

xiv Cf. 1996: 260-261.

xv Cf. Leslie (1996: 259).

xvi Cf. Leslie (1996: 258-259): “The thing to note is that the red ball can be treated either just as a red ball or else as a red-or-green ball. Bayes’s Rule applies in both cases. […] All this evidently continues to apply to when being-red-or-green is replaced by being-red-or-pink, or being-red-or-reddish”.

xvii This important aspect of the argument is also underlined in Delahaye (1996). It is also the main theme of Sober (2003).

xviii I thank Nick Bostrom for useful discussion on the reference class problem, and Daniel Andler, Jean-Paul Delahaye, John Leslie, Claude Panaccio, Elliott Sober, and an anonymous referee for the Journal of Philosophical Research, for helpful comments on earlier drafts.