Schizophrenia is often associated with other physical and mental problems. Generalized anxiety disorder is notably one of the comorbid disorders which is often linked to schizophrenia. The association of polythematic delusions and of ideas resulting from generalized anxiety disorder complicates the exercise of the corresponding cognitive therapy, for the resulting ideas are most often inextricably intertwined. In what follows, we endeavour to propose a methodology for the differential treatment of polythematic delusions inherent to schizophrenia when combined with ideas originating from generalized anxiety disorder. We propose, with regard to the corresponding content of delusions, an analysis which allows under certain conditions, to separate the content associated with polythematic delusions and the one that relates to generalized anxiety disorder, in order to facilitate the exercise of the corresponding cognitive therapy.
Differential Cognitive Treatment of Polythematic Delusions and Generalised Anxiety Disorder
Generalized anxiety disorder is a comorbid disorder which is commonly associated with schizophrenia. Such co-morbidity is likely to render more complex and difficult the corresponding cognitive therapy. In what follows, we strive to provide a methodology to allow for a differential treatment of polythematic delusions inherent to schizophrenia when associated with generalized anxiety disorder. We describe then, based on the content of the corresponding delusions, an analysis which allows, under certain conditions, to separate the content relating to the polythematic delusions and the one that concerns generalized anxiety disorder, in order to facilitate the implementation of the corresponding cognitive therapies.
Schizophrenia and co-morbidity
One of the difficulties inherent in the treatment of schizophrenia is the frequent co-morbidity that relates to the disease. This comorbidity bears either on physical conditions, or other psychiatric disorders. A co-morbidity of schizophrenia with physical [Sim et al affections. 2006] or neuropsychiatric disorders such as Tourette’s syndrome [Kerbeshiana et al. 2009], has then been observed. It was also found co-morbidity with other psychiatric disorders, which is very common [Bermanzohn 2000]. A significant co-morbidity has been ascertained in particular with depression (25%) [Bressan et al. 2003, Kim et al. 2008] and obsessive-compulsive disorder (26.50%) [Berman et al. 1995 Guillem et al. 2009]. Similarly, comorbidity within the sphere of anxiety disorders turns out to be quite common [Cosoff & Hafner, 1998, Braga et al. 2004]. It was thus demonstrated high rates of comorbidity with agoraphobia (8.20%) [Goodwin et al. 2002], panic disorder (13.80%) [Pallanti et al. 2004], generalized anxiety disorder (GAD), social phobia (13.30%) [Tibbo et al. 2003] or a specific phobia (13.60%) [Goodwin et al. 2002]. However, the co-morbidity of schizophrenia with certain disorders, such as intermittent explosive disorder, seems to have been little studied.
The comorbidity of schizophrenia with other psychiatric disorders does not lack to pose several problems in the treatment of the disease. First, such comorbidity is a factor that makes it difficult to improve the health status of the patient [Sim et al. 2006]. Second, the comorbidity of schizophrenia with other psychiatric disorders raises some specific issues that are important for cognitive and behavioural therapy of schizophrenia. Thus, the frequent comorbidity of schizophrenia with one or more associated disorders, suggests that it might be useful to adapt the corresponding cognitive therapy. In this sense, it may be useful to distinguish cognitive therapy targeted to polythematic delusions, from the therapy related to the comorbid disorders encountered in the patient. In any event, the introduction of a differential treatment of schizophrenia and comorbid disorders has specific aspects that should be highlighted. Such differential treatment requires for the therapist that the different disorders are well defined and especially that the therapist can distinguish within the patient’s speech what is relevant to the specific disorder that he/she aims to treat. In this context, the association of two or more disorders does not fail to create some confusion, for the patient’s delusions are often inextricably linked to ideas that arise from the co-morbid disorder(s). Thus, in the words of the patient, it is worth distinguishing between what is actual symptoms of schizophrenia (essentially polythematic delusions) and what results from the associated comorbid disorders, such as: depression, TAG, body dysmorphic disorder, social phobia, special phobia. This complex situation has the effect of making more difficult the corresponding cognitive therapy.
The difficulties just mentioned apply especially when schizophrenia is associated in patients with GAD, for which a co-morbidity rate of 12% [Cosoff & Hafner 1998] and 16.70% [Tibbo et al. 2003] were found. We propose, in what follows, to interest ourselves in the comorbidity of schizophrenia and TAG, and to proceed to describe in detail a methodology for distinguishing among the patient’s delusions, the content resulting from polythematic delusions proper from what is inherent to the TAG.
Instances of differentiation: polythematic delusions and anxiogenous ideas
The association of the content of these delusional ideas met in schizophrenia and anxiogenous ideas inherent to TAG may take different forms. For ease of analysis, we will work to identify certain stereotyped forms, among the mixed ideas resulting from this association. We shall use the classically defined delusions (delusions of reference, of telepathy, of thought-projection, of influence, or of control) and anxiogenous ideas whose structure is that of the projection of a negative future event. Let us consider then the mixed ideas likely to be encountered in the context of the association of polythematic delusions associated with schizophrenia and GAD (with the following abbreviations: R for reference, T for telepathy, P for thought-projection, I for influence, C for control):
(R1)
“Next week, TV presenters will again talk about me”.
(T1)
“I am sure that in five minutes, the neighbour will again comment on my thoughts”.
(P1)
“I am sure that soon, people in the street will again start yelling because they are disturbed by my thoughts”.
(I1)
“Tomorrow, I will again create an accident, because of the disruption that I create in others with my bad mood”.
(C1)
“I am sure that when they will arrive, the neighbours will still make me break things by controlling me”.
These are mental constructs that combine both delusions which are specific to schizophrenia and anxiety ideas resulting from TAG (the structure of the latter being that of the anticipation of the occurrence of a future event of a negative nature). It is worth at this stage determining the structure of these mixed ideas in order to highlight what constitutes polythematic delusions proper and what is inherent in the TAG. Thus, in (R1) is contained, first, the delusion that the media talk about the patient, which is an instance of the delusion of reference. Second, the expectation that a negative event will occur, i.e. the media will speak again about the patient, is also present in (R1). Such an anticipation on a future event of a negative nature, has a special structure, which consists in the projection into the future of the occurrence of a negative event concerning the patient, even in the absence of an objective basis. This is one of the manifestations of the role played in TAG by expectations on indeterminate situations related to future events [Butler & Mathews 1987]. Most often, the patient considers a future event as certain, even though the probability of the event in question’s occurrence is much lower. Such anxiogenous idea has the structure below [Franceschi 2008a] (the patient’s anxiogenous idea occurs at time T0, with T0 <T1):
(A)
at time T1, the event E of a negative nature, will occur
anxiogenous idea
Given the above, we can now decompose the mixed idea (R1) in two separate ideas i.e. on the one hand, the delusion of reference and on the other hand, the projection of a negative future event:
(R)
“Television and the media speak about me”
delusion of reference
(AR)
at time T1 (“Next week”) the event E (“The presenters de television will speak about me”) of a negative nature, will occur
mixed anxiogenous idea
At this stage, it is now possible to apply a principle of cognitive therapy specific to TAG to the resulting anxiogenous mixed idea, by considering alternative hypotheses to the occurrence of the negative event, by notably considering the hypothesis that other events, of a positive nature, may occur. It also turns out that the same analysis can be applied to mixed propositions (T1), (P1), (I1) and (C1), in the following way:
(T)
“The neighbours know the least of my thoughts”
delusion of telepathy
(AT)
at time T1 (“by five minutes”) the event E (“the neighbour will comment on my thoughts”) of a negative nature, will occur
mixed anxiogenous idea
(P)
“People react according to what I think and start screaming”
thought projection delusion
(AP)
at time T1 (“in a moment”) the event E (“people in the street will begin to cry because they are disturbed by my thoughts”) of a negative nature, will occur
mixed anxiogenous idea
(I)
“People are disturbed by my thoughts”
delusion of influence
(AI)
at time T1 (“tomorrow”) the event E (“I’m going to cause an accident, because of the disruption that I create in others with my bad mood”) of a negative nature, will occur
mixed anxiogenous idea
(C)
“I have feelings and emotions according to what people do”
delusion of control
(AC)
at time T1 (“when they will arrive”) the event E (“the neighbours will make me break things by controlling me”) of a negative nature, will occur
mixed anxiogenous idea
However, it turns out that the application of a principle cognitive therapy inherent to GAD to the mixed anxiety ideas resulting from the above analysis, is likely to present a problem. Indeed, a questioning of the form “Is it certain that the television will still talk to you tomorrow?” or “Isn’t it possible that television will not speak about you tomorrow? may give the impression that the therapist adheres to the patient’s delusional ideas of reference, which might be likely to strengthen them. To avoid this problem, it may be useful to eliminate the delusional content in the mixed anxiety-provoking idea. For once such removal is done, the principle of cognitive therapy inherent to GAD can then be applied directly to the residual anxiety idea without the aforementioned drawback begin faced. The methodology we propose to transform the mixed anxiety idea into a pure anxiety idea is based on the process of formation of the patient’s delusions. The development of the delusional ideas (R) (T) (P), (I) and (C) is carried starting from the primary delusional arguments, based on the attribution by the patient of a causal relationship when faced with the occurrence of two quasi-simultaneous events [Hemsley 1992 Franceschi 2008b]. Such primary delusional arguments have the following structure (the symbol ∴ denotes the conclusion):
(R1)
in T1 I was drinking an aperitif
premiss1
(R2)
in T2 the presenter of the show said: “Stop drinking !”
premiss2
(R3)
∴ in T2 the presenter of the show said: “Stop drinking !” because in T1 I was drinking an aperitif
conclusion
(T1)
in T1 I thought of Jacques “What an idiot !”
premiss1
(T2)
in T2 I heard Jacques say: “Enough!”
premiss2
(T3)
∴ in T2 I heard Jacques say, “Enough! “Because in T1 I thought of him,”What an idiot!”
conclusion
(P1)
in T1 I thought of someone who passed on the street “is badly dressed!”
premiss1
(P2)
in T2 I heard someone who passed on the street shout
premiss2
(P3)
∴ in T2 I heard someone who passed in the street screaming because in T1 I thought of of him “He’s badly dressed!”
conclusion
(I1)
in T1 I had a very bad mood
premiss1
(I2)
in T2 I heard there was a car accident in the street
premiss2
(I3)
∴ in T2 there was a car accident in the street because in T1 I was in a very bad mood
conclusion
(C1)
in T1 the neighbour has moved
premiss1
(C2)
in T2 I broke a glass
premiss2
(C3)
∴ in T2 I broke a glass because in T1 the neighbour has moved
conclusion
Such a structure from primary delusional arguments reveals that in instances of primary arguments of reference, of telepathy, of thought projection and of influence, an internal event to the patient (thought, emotion, feeling, action) slightly precedes an external event, in the following manner:
(α1)
in T1 the internal event E1 has occurred
premiss1
(α2)
in T2 the external event E2 has occurred
premiss2
(α3)
∴ in T2 the external event E2 has occurred because in T1 the internal event E1 has occurred
conclusion
In contrast, at the level of the instances of primary arguments of control, it is the event which is external to the patient that precedes an internal event:
(β1)
in T1 the external event E1 has occurred
premiss1
(β2)
in T2 the internal event E2 has occurred
premiss2
(β3)
∴ in T2 the internal event E2 has occurred because in T1 the exernal event E1 has occurred
conclusion
In this context, the elimination of the delusional content from mixed delusions can then be performed. For this, one eliminates from the mixed anxiogenous idea the mere idea of causality, by only retaining the event which constitutes the object of the anxiogenous idea, in the following way:
(AI)
at time T1 (“tomorrow”) the event E (“I’m going to create an accident, because of the disturbance that I create in others with my bad mood”) of a negative nature, will occur
mixed anxiogenous idea
(BI)
at time T1 (“tomorrow”) the event E (“there will be an accident in the street”) of a negative nature, will occur
pure anxiogenous idea
The methodology used here is thus to eliminate the delusional content in the speech of the patient and replace it with factual content, to which we can then apply a classical form of cognitive therapy for GAD, based on the consideration of alternative hypotheses: “Isn’t it possible that no accident occurs on the street tomorrow? “(I); “Isn’t it possible that tomorrow you could not break your glass? “(C); “Can’t we consider that no passer-by shouts in the street just now? “(P). Such formulation has thus the advantage of enabling the direct implementation of the very principle of the cognitive therapy inherent to TAG without facing the above-mentioned drawback.
Conclusion
In cognitive therapy of schizophrenia raises the question of the appropriate treatment of comorbid disorders associated with it. Regarding particularly GAD, which is often associated with schizophrenia, several questions arise as well. The first question is thus whether it is appropriate that two different therapists take care one of the therapy for GAD, and the other of the therapy for delusions. A second question, in this context, is whether it is better to implement the GAD therapy before that targeted at delusions [17,18]. The answer to these questions is beyond the scope of this study, but it may be important in the strategy implemented for cognitive therapy of schizophrenia.
At this point, it turns out that the usefulness of the above analysis it that it allows for simplifying the cognitive therapy in the case where there is a comorbid schizophrenia and TAG, in that it separates in the content of the original complex discourse of the patient, what is delusions proper and what is inherent in the TAG. This permits the isolation of a simplified discourse, to which can then be applied independently either the principle inherent to cognitive therapy for TAG, or the one that relates to delusions. This results in a second interest, in that it can help, if necessary, to two different therapists to take care of each cognitive therapy for GAD and delusions. Finally, a third interest is that it allows to make use of specific strategies. One such strategy is for example to implement cognitive therapy for GAD before cognitive therapy delusions. Is it better in effect when there exists in the patient a co-morbidity between schizophrenia and TAG, to implement cognitive therapy for GAD before, after or at the same the therapy for delusions? The above discussion does not lead to prefer one or other strategic option, but they can still be reformulated in terms of testable hypotheses. The first testable hypothesis that emerges is that the implementation of cognitive therapy for GAD, irrespective of cognitive therapy for delusions, could have a positive effect on symptoms of schizophrenia themselves. The second testable hypothesis is that the resulting cognitive therapy for delusions themselves could be more effective if it was implemented after a cognitive therapy for GAD has been achieved and demonstrated effective.
References
[1] Berman, I., Kalinowski, A., Berman, S.M., Lengua, J., Green, A.I. Obsessive and compulsive symptoms in chronic schizophrenia. Comprehensive Psychiatry 1995; 36: 6-10.
[2] Bermanzohn P.C., Porto L., Arlow P.B., Pollack S., Stronger R., Siris S.G. Hierarchical diagnosis in chronic schizophrenia: a clinical study of co-occurring syndromes. Schizophrenia Bulletin 2000; 26: 517–525.
[3] Braga R., Petrides G., Figueira I. Anxiety Disorders in Schizophrenia, Comprehensive Psychiatry 2004; 45(6): 460-468.
[4] Bressan, R.A., Chaves, A.C., Pilowsky, L.S., Shirakawa, I., Mari, J.J. Depressive episodes in stable schizophrenia: critical evaluation of the DSM-IV and ICD-110 diagnostic criteria. Psychiatry Research 2003; 117: 47–56.
[5] Butler G et Mathews A. Anticipatory anxiety and risk perception. Cognitive Therapy and Research 1987; 11: 551-565.
[6] Cosoff S.J., Hafner R.J. The prevalence of co-morbid anxiety in schizophrenia, schizoaffective disorder and bipolar disorder. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 1998; 32: 67-72.
[7] Franceschi P. Théorie des distorsions cognitives : application à l’anxiété généralisée, Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive 2008a; 18: 127-131. English translation.
[8] Franceschi P. Une défense logique du modèle de Maher pour les délires polythématiques. Philosophiques 2008b; 35(2): 451-475. English translation.
[9] Goodwin R., Lyons J., McNally R. Panic attacks in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Research 2002; 58: 213-220.
[10] Guillem F., Satterthwaite J., Pampoulova T., Stip E. Relationship between psychotic and obsessive compulsive symptoms in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Research 2009; 115: 358-62.
[11] Hemsley D. Disorders of perception and cognition in schizophrenia. Revue européenne de Psychologie Appliquée 1992; 42(2): 105-114.
[12] Kerbeshiana J., Pengb C.Z., Burd L. Tourette syndrome and comorbid early-onset schizophrenia. Journal of Psychosomatic Research 2009; 67: 515-523.
[13] Kim S.W., Kim S.J., Yoon B.H., Kim J.M., Shin I.S., Hwang M., Yoon J.S. Diagnostic validity of assessment scales for depression in patients with schizophrenia. Psychiatry Research 2006; 144: 57-63.
[14] Kingdon D. et Turkington D. Cognitive-behavioural Therapy of Schizophrenia, New York: Guilford, 1994.
[15] Kingdon, D. et Turkington, D. Cognitive Therapy of Schizophrenia, New York, London: Guilford, 2005.
[16] Pallanti S., Quercioli L., Hollander E. Social anxiety in outpatients with schizophrenia: a relevant cause of disability. Am J Psychiatry 2004; 161: 53-58.
[17] Sim K., Chan Y.H., Chua T.H., Mahendran R., Chong S.A., McGorry P. Physical comorbidity, insight, quality of life and global functioning in first episode schizophrenia: A 24-month, longitudinal outcome study. Schizophrenia Research 2006; 88: 82-89.
[18] Tibbo P., Swainson J., Chue P., LeMelledo JM. Prevalence and relationship to delusions and hallucinations of anxiety disorders in schizophrenia. Depress Anxiety 2003;17: 65-72.
This article aims to contribute to cognitive therapy of polythematic delusions by proposing a preliminary step to the implementation of traditional cognitive therapy, based on the construction of alternative hypotheses to delusions and testing of the latter. This additional step resides in the construction in the patient of the necessary skills to use the general experimentalist method of knowledge acquisition. Such an approach is based on the contrast between the logico-theoretical and the experimentalist turn of mind. Some elements such as to allow any such construction in the patient are then described and analyzed.
Polythematic Delusions and Logico-Theoretical vs. Experimentalist Turn of Mind
Classical cognitive therapy targeted at polythematic delusions associated with schizophrenia is based on the search for evidence related to delusional ideas and the construction of alternative hypotheses to the latter. This article aims to contribute to cognitive therapy for polythematic delusions by proposing a preliminary step to this classical cognitive therapy. Such a step aims to strengthen the patient’s ability to use the general approach of experimentalist type for knowledge acquisition—an approach which is based on the opposition between the theoretical-logical and the experimentalist turn of mind. Some elements such as to enable the reinforcement of such a capability in the patient are thus described and analyzed.
Theoretical-logical vs. experimentalist turn of mind
Cognitive therapy of schizophrenia aimed at polythematic delusions includes a component mainly oriented toward teaching the patient skills for search of evidence relating to the ideas associated with polythematic delusions, as well as the construction of alternative hypotheses (Kingdon & Turkington, 1994, 2002). It consists thus, on the one hand, of teaching the patient how to construct alternative hypotheses to delusions such as “television is talking about me”, “a satellite sends me thoughts”, “aliens are plotting against me”, etc., and secondly to encourage him/her to test both delusions and the associated alternative hypotheses, in order to validate or invalidate them. Such an approach applies then, in a specific way, to polythematic delusions which are inherent to the patient, and the corresponding alternative hypotheses. At this point, we can observe that this approach is associated with a general methodology of the same nature, which is not based on the very polythematic delusions inherent to the patient. Such an approach proves then grounded on the acquisition of the general ability to build up alternative hypotheses and to carry out tests on different hypotheses. Unlike traditional therapy that bears specifically on the content of the polythematic delusions, such an approach presents a general nature and proves likely to refer to any type of hypotheses. We can describe the general nature of such an approach as experimentalist.
We can observe here that the fact that classical cognitive therapy is based on strengthening in the patient the ability to develop alternative hypotheses to delusions and to perform tests on them, implicitly relies on the fact that such an ability is low or deficient in the patient, at least with respect to the delusions developed by the latter. We suggest then to make the wider assumption that the overall ability to develop alternative hypotheses and tests in order to validate or invalidate ideas, could be low or deficient in the patient, and that the problem encountered with delusions represents the visible part of a more general problem that is inherent to the patient. We also propose that the two above-mentioned elements (test implementation and construction of alternative hypotheses) are also part of an overall ability that also includes additional elements, and can be defined as the ability to implement the experimentalist method of knowledge acquisition.
For the purpose of the present study, it is necessary to further clarify the very notion of general methodology of experimentalist nature. To this end, it is worth contrasting first the experimentalist turn of mind with the logico-theoretical one. Such opposition allows for a better understanding of the experimentalist approach itself. This opposition corresponds essentially to a classical opposition in science, which contrasts two particular styles that each lead to acquisition of knowledge. Whereas the method of experimentalist inspiration proceeds by elaborating hypotheses and testing them, the logico-theoretical method proceeds by logical deduction or induction from a set of knowledge of which the one who exerts it strives to maintain consistency. Both methods, on the scientific level, each have their supporters and detractors. However, advances in knowledge are to be credited to both methods, which ultimately appear as complementary and may eventually be regarded as two ways of accessing scientific knowledge.
The opposition between experimentalist vs. logico-theoretical turn of mind is not limited, however, to the scientific field. Indeed, such opposition has a more general scope and also applies to any body of knowledge, including that resulting from the process of acquiring information and knowledge concerning everyday life. In this context, the logico-theoretical turn of mind notably proceeds by deduction, by trying to acquire knowledge in a logical way; it is aimed at explaining and interpreting facts and phenomena. Such an approach is underpinned by a concern for consistency of the whole corresponding set of knowledge, by also trying to identify and remedy any internal contradiction. The logico-theoretical approach may also proceed by inductive reasoning, thus making use of inductive generalization. In addition, when an internal contradiction is found, thus rendering the whole set of knowledge inconsistent, the one who proceeds in a logico-theoretical way strives to quickly restore this consistency, by possibly modifying some elements that are part of the overall knowledge at his/her disposal. Conversely, the one who proceeds with the help of the experimentalist approach is basically concerned with validating theories and hypotheses, through experimentation, testing, and search for evidence. He/she is then concerned with only retaining ultimately that knowledge that has been validated by experience and whose strength lies in the evidence which has been thus collected.
Thus characterized through their opposition, it is no less apparent that each of the experimentalist or logico-theoretical method of knowledge acquisition has its drawbacks when pushed to the extreme. When applied in excess, the logico-theoretical method thus leads to risky speculation and lack of evidence, to unrealistic and disconnected from the reality viewpoints. Conversely, experimentation pushed to the extreme leads to knowledge that lacks power of abstraction, explanatory and predictive power, and does not allow understanding of the data and the phenomena. In order to better emphasize the related notions and also better highlight the relationship with the different neighboring concepts, it is worth providing some additional insight over the opposition between experimentalist and logico-theoretical methodology. We shall propose then to make use of the matrices of concepts described in Franceschi (2002), which allow to emphasize the relationships between some given concepts. A matrix of concepts thus consists of six concepts, distributed along two dual poles: A and Ā. Each of these poles admits of respectively a concept of neutral A0, Ā0, positive (A+, Ā+) and negative (A–, Ā–) nature. In total, the matrix consists of the six following concepts: A+, A0, A–, Ā+, Ā0, Ā–.
Figure 1. Structure of a matrix of concepts
Among the main relationships that can be defined between concepts of the same matrix, it is worth citing: (i) the duality relation, between two neutral concepts of different poles: A0 and Ā0; (ii) the relation of antinomy (or of contrary) between two concepts that are not neutral (that is to say, positive or negative) of opposite polarity and of different poles: A+ and Ā–, as well as A– and Ā+; (iii) the complementary relationship between two concepts of same polarity (positive or negative) and of different poles: A+ and Ā+ as well as A– and Ā–. For example, the matrix of concepts corresponding to the concepts of courage, cowardice and temerity is thus as follows:
Figure 2. An instance of a matrix of concepts
At this step, we are in a position to construct the matrix of concepts that applies to the opposition between theoretical-logical and experimentalist turn of mind. Each of these concepts presents an intrinsic neutral nature, but is likely to give rise to a positive and a negative form. The corresponding matrix of concepts is thus the following:
Figure 3. The matrix of concepts associated with the theoretical-logical/experimentalist turn of mind
We can see here that the theoretical-logical turn of mind presents a positive form which leads to fruitful theorization, and a negative form that engenders unrealistic ideas and hazardous speculations. Conversely, the experimentalist turn of mind has a positive form which entails the solidity of knowledge and the search for evidence, and a negative form which leads to extreme empiricism, associated with lack of understanding and absence of explanation.
General application of the experimentalist methodology
The foregoing analysis leads to the hypothesis that it might be advisable to rebuild preliminarily in the patient the general ability to implement the experimentalist method of knowledge acquisition, before applying it later in a specific way to polythematic delusions. Cognitive therapy targeted at polythematic delusions would accordingly involve two phases: the first aimed at restoring in the patient the functional ability to the experimentalist general approach; and the second intended to implement the latter, in a specific way, by applying it to polythematic delusions. Several arguments seem to lean in favor of such an option. Firstly, it seems preferable that the patient be first convinced of the merits of the experimentalist method of acquiring knowledge, even before applying it to polythematic delusions. In other words, it seems better than the patient has himself/herself acquired first the belief that the theoretical-experimental method is effective and useful before applying it to the specific topics corresponding to delusions. Second, it also seems preferable that the patient would acquire a prior good practice and be exercised first to the experimentalist method on external, neutral and impersonal facts, before applying it to his/her own delusions which present for him/her an eminently emotional, personal and sensitive nature. Presumably also the choice of topics external to the patient should be such as to enable him/her to mobilize his/her cognitive abilities optimally. Thirdly, it is reasonable to think that the fact of applying the experimentalist methodology exclusively to the content of polythematic delusions, without possessing at the same time such a general ability might have some disadvantages. One of these drawbacks may lie in the fact that the patient could quickly rebuild some other delusions from other themes than those usual to him/her. Finally, it is worth mentioning that the acquisition and the general practice of the experimentalist methodology on topics that are completely independent of the content itself of the polythematic delusions should be non-confrontational, and likely to preserve the therapeutic alliance.
At this point, it is possible to sketch an outline of what could consist such a preliminary part of cognitive therapy for polythematic delusions. This last part would include a component targeted at learning the construction of alternative hypotheses, and a component designed to the learning of testing different hypotheses. However, in order to form a coherent whole, it is reasonable to think that this part of the therapy should also include an explanation of a number of related concepts, among which we can mention: the distinction between fact and hypothesis; the notion of proof; the distinction between evidence and conviction; the notion of validation and invalidation of a hypothesis; the distinction between fact and interpretation of fact; the distinction between fact and perception of fact; the distinction between fact and fact narration; the construction of alternative hypotheses; the development of tests with regard to a hypothesis; the causal relationship between facts; the proof of the causal relationship; the distinction between facts whose cause is intentional or non-intentional; the notion of explanation of a given phenomenon. Several of these elements, especially those related to the construction of alternative hypotheses, are integral part of the training program for metacognition developed by Moritz et al. (2010, 2011).
It is also useful to point out here several areas where the above-mentioned principles could be put into practice. These areas are potentially very diverse, but it is however possible to describe more accurately some of them, which relate to electronics and computer science. In the field of electronics first, consideration could be given to take an interest in electronic circuits (or computer simulations thereof) and their operation. Thus, the patient’s attention could focus on the operational problems of such and such circuit and especially on the search for causes of observed failures (e.g. the fact that a led indicator does not light up). It will then be necessary to formulate different hypotheses regarding the cause of the malfunction, which may relate to different circuit components (transistors, power supply, the led indicator itself, etc..) which can then be tested in order to be validated or invalidated, and later give rise, depending on the test results to other hypotheses, etc..
The field of computer science, second, could offer various fields of applications, especially in programming. We may notably consider a computer program that is supposed to produce a given result but has a defect in its execution, due to a “bug”. It will be then a matter of accurately determining the cause of this bug i.e., of finding the specific instruction within the program, which is responsible. The patient would thus be required to make assumptions regarding the specific instruction in the program among instr1, instr2, instr3, …, instrn, which is at the origin of the bug and to test successively the latter. This will lead for example to eliminate the instruction instr1 of which it will be assumed that it is the origin of the bug and to test the program without it, etc.. If the latter test invalidates the hypothesis, such an approach will then lead to test another instruction instr2, and so on.
Specific application of the experimentalist methodology to polythematic delusions
Classical cognitive therapy of schizophrenia (Kingdon & Turkington, 1994; Beck & Rector, 2000; Kingdon & Turkington, 2002) aims to gradually reduce the degree of belief in the patient’s delusions. For this purpose, the therapist suggests to the patient, in a spirit of dialogue of Socratic inspiration to build alternative hypotheses. He/she also teaches to the patient the process of testing the various competing hypotheses by seeking evidence, thus allowing to confirm or refute them.
It seems useful, at this point, to describe the different stages that occur differently depending on the level—primary, secondary or tertiary—of the corresponding delusions (Franceschi (2008). We shall consider in turn each of these levels. We propose to analyze here the delusions of reference, given that the analysis can be transposed to the delusions of influence, of telepathy, of thought projection or of control.
A primary delusional argument of reference, first, has the following structure (the symbol ∴ denotes the conclusion):
(R1)
in T1 I was drinking an aperitif
premiss1
(R2)
in T2 the presenter of the show said: “Don’t drink!”
premiss2
(R3)
∴ in T2 the presenter of the show said: “Don’t drink!” because in T1 I was drinking an aperitif
conclusion
The corresponding delusional idea is that according to which the presenter said in T2: “Don’t drink!” because the patient has been drinking an aperitif in T1. The structure of such a delusional idea is as follows: the event E1 (in T1 I was drinking an aperitif) is the cause of the event E2 (in T2 the presenter of the show said: “Don’t drink!”). In this case, the logical structure of the alternative hypothesis to the delusional conclusion (R3) is that the event E1 which is internal to the patient is not the cause of the external event E2. The different alternative hypotheses identify then themselves with alternative causes to the event E2. Thus, the delusional conclusion (R3) may be confronted with an alternative hypothesis such as: the presenter said in T2: “Don’t drink!” because the script of this television program contained it. Another alternative hypothesis is that it is the assistant presenter who suggested to say it, etc..
One may think, however, that the fact of proposing to the patient alternative hypotheses to the delusional conclusion (R3) just mentioned, could prove insufficient. In effect, the patient’s delusional idea that the event E1 internal to the patient is the cause of the external event E2, not only has the nature of a hypothesis, but also has explanatory power, in the sense that it constitutes an explanation of the fact that appears bewildering to the patient that the presenter has said: “Do not drink!” immediately after the patient has been drinking an aperitif. In comparison, the fact that the event E2 internal to the patient is not the cause of the external event E2, constitutes an alternative hypothesis, but proves devoid of such explanatory power. For this reason, we believe that the mere statement, under this form, of the latter alternative hypothesis should not suffice to gain the support of the patient. For it is necessary to submit to the latter an alternative hypothesis to the conclusion (R3), which is also able to provide an explanation for the rapid succession of events E1 and E2. In this context, an alternative hypothesis that also allows to provide an explanation for the rapid succession of two phenomena, is the one according to which the external event E2 succeeded immediately after internal event E1, by the effect of a coincidence. Under these conditions, the patient faces two competing hypotheses that may explain the rapid and disturbing sequence of events E1 and E2: the first hypothesis being that E1 is the cause of E2; and the second being that the rapid succession of E1 and E2 is but a coincidence.
Secondly, the structure of secondary delusional arguments of reference is as follows:
(R1)
in T2 the presenter of the show spoke according to what I was doing
premiss1
(R2)
in T4 the presenter of the show spoke according to what I felt
premiss2
(R3)
in T6 the presenter of the show spoke according to what I was doing
premiss3
(R…)
…
…
(R10)
∴ the presenters of the shows speak according to what I do or what I feel
conclusion
The corresponding delusional idea of reference is then the conclusion (R10) that the presenters of the shows speak according to what the patient makes or feels. The conclusion (R10) is of an inductive nature and constitutes a generalization from the several instances (R1), (R2), (R3), … Here, the logical structure of the alternative hypothesis to the conclusion (R10) is that the presenters of the shows do not speak according to what the patient makes. But in the same way as above, such a hypothesis proves devoid of explanatory power. In contrast, the alternative hypothesis, which has an additional explanatory power, is the fact that by the effect of coincidences, the rapid succession of two events that may give the impression of the existence of a relationship causality, occurs frequently.
Finally, the ternary delusional arguments of reference exhibit the following structure:
(R10)
∴ the presenters of the shows speak according to what I do or what I feel
premiss
(R11)
∴ television speaks about me
conclusion
The ternary delusional idea of reference is the one according to which television speaks of the patient. The logical structure of the alternative hypothesis is the one under which television does not speak of the patient. However, in the same way as above, such a hypothesis does not possess in itself an explanatory power. For the conclusion (R11) has, in the patient’s mind, an explanatory function to the succession of events that he/she experienced. It proves thus necessary, at this stage, to propose an alternative explanation, which resides in the fact that through the effect of coincidences, it frequently happens that the patient’s internal events are immediately followed by external events, which can give the impression that there is a causal relationship between the two successive events. However, it may be pointed out to the patient, there is a much larger number of pairs of successive events that are not consistent with a causal relationship. It is indeed a common attitude to pay attention only to the succession of two events that could be meaningful, even though it occurs every day many more successions of two unmeaningful events and to which one does not pay any attention. This appears as a special case of misinterpretation of random data (Bressan, 2002).
Conclusion
At this point, it is worth translating the previous elements in terms of testable hypotheses by the clinician. This leads thus to test the hypothesis that cognitive therapy applied to polythematic delusions may be more effective if it included two successive steps: the first advocated by the present study that aims to reconstruct the patient’s general ability to acquisition of knowledge through the practice of the experimentalist method; and the second, classically defined by cognitive therapy of schizophrenia that leads to apply specifically the skills thus acquired to the content of polythematic delusions.
Finally, it is possible to synthesize the ideas expressed in Franceschi (2011) regarding the co-morbidity of schizophrenia with the elements resulting from the present study. We are thus able to define the different stages of the resulting process for cognitive therapy of delusions inherent to schizophrenia. This would mean thus, in a first step, determining the co-morbid disorders (specific phobias, generalized anxiety disorder, social phobia, intermittent explosive disorder, etc.). associated in the patient with the delusional ideas and to apply first a specific cognitive therapy. In a second step, it would mean applying the learning phase of the above-mentioned method experimentalist of a general nature. Finally, in a final phase, it should be proceeded as indicated by classical cognitive therapy, by applying specifically the experimentalist methodology to the content of delusions. This can be translated as follows in terms of testable hypotheses: a cognitive therapy of schizophrenia that would proceed according to these three successive stages could be more effective than classical cognitive therapy.
References
Beck, A. (2002). Delusions: A Cognitive perspective. Journal of Cognitive Psychotherapy, 16–4, 455–468.
Bressan, P. (2002). The connection between random sequences, everyday coincidences, and belief in the paranormal. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 16, 17–34.
Franceschi, P. (2002). Une classe de concepts. Semiotica, 139–1/4, 211–226. English translation.
Franceschi, P. (2008). Une défense logique du modèle de Maher pour les délires polythématiques. Philosophiques, 35-2, 451–475. English translation.
Franceschi, P. (2011). Traitement cognitif différentiel des délires polythématiques et du trouble anxieux généralisé. Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 21–4, 121–125. English translation.
Kingdon, D. & Turkington, D. (1994). Cognitive-behavioural Therapy of Schizophrenia. New York: Guilford.
Kingdon, D. & Turkington, D. (Eds.) (2002). The Case Study Guide to Cognitive Behaviour Therapy of Psychosis. Chichester: Wiley.
Moritz, S., Woodward, T. S., & Metacognition Study Group. (2010). Metacognitive training for schizophrenia (MCT). Manual (4th ed.), Hamburg: VanHam Campus.
Moritz, S., Kerstan, A., Veckenstedt, R., Randjbar, S., Vitzthum, F., Schmidt, C., Heise, M., Woodward, T.S. (2011). Further evidence for the efficacy of a metacognitive group training in schizophrenia. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 49, 151–157.
In this paper, we describe several factors that can contribute, from the patient’s viewpoint, to the plausibility of psychotic hallucinations. We sketch then a Plausibility of Hallucinations Scale, consisting of a 50-item questionnaire, which aims at evaluating the degree of plausibility of hallucinations. We also emphasize the utility of pointing out to the patient the several factors that contribute to the plausibility of his/her hallucinations, in the context of cognitive therapy for schizophrenia.
This paper is cited in:
Mark Grimshaw, Tom Garner, Sonic Virtuality: Sound as Emergent Perception, New York: Oxford University Press, 2015
Charlotte Aynsworth, Daniel Collerton, Robert Dudley, Measures of visual hallucinations: Review and recommendations, Clinical Psychology Review, Volume 57, 2017, Pages 164-182
I. de Chazeron, B. Pereirae, I. Chereau-Boudete, G. Broussee, D. Misdrahie, G. Fénelone, A.-M. Tronchee, R. Schwane, C. Lançone, A. Marquese, B. Debillye, F. Durife, P.M. Llorca, Validation of a Psycho-Sensory Hallucinations Scale (PSAS) in schizophrenia and Parkinson’s disease, Schizophrenia Research, Volume 161, Issues 2-3, Pages 269–276, 2015
On the plausibility of psychotic hallucinations
Cognitive therapy of hallucinations is part of cognitive therapy for schizophrenia. Several accounts of cognitive therapy of hallucinations have been described in the literature (Chadwick et al.,1996; Rector & Beck, 2002; Kingdon & Turkington, 2005). On the one hand, Chadwick et al. (1996) stress the importance of the ABC model for cognitive therapy of hallucinations: the hallucinations are the activating events, which engender cognitions, which in turn yield emotional distress and anger. By working on beliefs about the voices, they primary aim at reducing the negative emotions which are the consequences of automatic thoughts following the occurrence of hallucinations. Chadwick et al. also have a special emphasis on the omnipotence and omniscience of the voices. On the other hand, Kingdon & Turkington (2005) propose the cognitive model of hallucinations as an alternative explanation for the voices: auditory hallucinations are the patient’s automatic thoughts that are perceived as originating from outside the patient’s mind. Kingdon & Turkington weigh the available evidence for both competing explanations and finally work on reattribution of auditory hallucinations. Rector & Beck (2002) take a similar stance, and stress that the final aim of the therapy “is to help patients recognize that the voices simply reflect either their own attitudes about themselves or those they imagine others to have about them”.
The purpose of the present paper is to contribute to cognitive therapy for schizophrenia by focusing on the plausibility of psychotic hallucinations. Our concern will be with providing an account of complex hallucinations encountered in schizophrenia that stresses multiple factors which reinforce, from the patient’s viewpoint, the intrinsic plausibility of the hallucinations. The purpose of this paper is then to expose how hallucinations can seem plausible and credible to the patient. In section 1, we describe several factors that contribute to the plausibility of hallucinations occurring in schizophrenia. We sketch then in section 2 a scale which is designed to measure accurately the plausibility of hallucinations. In section 3, we point out what could be the impact on cognitive therapy for schizophrenia of the present account. Finally, we point out the limitations of the present study and some directions for further research.
1. Factors of plausibility of hallucinations
We shall enumerate in what follows several factors that can contribute, from the patient’s viewpoint, to the plausibility of the hallucinations that he/she experiences. Hallucinations are one major symptom of schizophrenia. According to DSM-IV, a hallucination is defined as “A sensory perception that has the compelling sense of reality of a true perception but that occurs without external stimulation of the relevant sensory organ”. (DSM-IV, p. 767). By plausibility, we mean the fact that the patient’s abnormal perceptions are seemingly attributable to an external source (usually, other people). The plausibility that results from certain phenomenological features of auditory hallucinations has notably been hinted at by Stephane et al. (2003):
(…) hearing “multiple voices” is associated with attribution of the “voices” to others, which is plausible intuitively as well. This indicates that the patients’ experiences of hallucinations could be understood, intuitively, based on common sense experiences of the world.
In this paper, we shall expand this idea, by pointing out that multiple factors are susceptible of congruently strengthening the patient’s conviction that his/her abnormal perceptions come from the external world.
Hallucinations come in a variety of modalities. In order to shed light on the factors that can lead to the plausibility of hallucinations occurring in schizophrenia, it is worth drawing first some useful distinctions.
1.1 Unimodal and multi-modal hallucinations
Let us consider, to begin with, the distinction between unimodal and multi-modal hallucinations. Unimodal hallucinations can be classified into five types, corresponding to our five sensory pathways: auditory, visual, olfactory, tactile and gustatory. Multi-modal hallucinations are made up of unimodal hallucinations of different types which occur simultaneously (or quasi-simultaneously). There are accordingly 26 combinations of multi-modal hallucinations (plus 5 unimodal ones). The latter can be enumerated exhaustively as follows (we also describe an instance of some common multi-modal cases, since it can be useful for explanatory purposes):
(ii) 2-modal: auditory-visual (“I saw x sitting on my bed and I heard him saying ‘Bastard!’”), auditory-olfactory (“I heard x saying ‘I will smoke a cigar! ’ and at this very moment I smell a taste of tobacco”), auditory-tactile (“I heard x saying ‘You will be stung by a scorpion!’ and at this very moment I felt a sharp sting of pain on my left arm”), auditory-gustatory, visual-olfactory (“I saw x on my bed smoking a cigar and I also smell the taste of tobacco”), visual-tactile (“I saw a scorpion on my left arm and at this very moment I felt a sharp sting of pain there”), visual-gustatory (“I saw blood dripping from my finger and it had the taste of blood when I put it on my tongue”), olfactory-tactile, olfactory-gustatory, tactile-gustatory
(iii) 3-modal: auditory-visual-olfactory, auditory-visual-tactile (“I heard x saying ‘You will be stung by a scorpion!’ and at this very moment I saw a scorpion on my left arm while feeling a sharp sting of pain there”), auditory-visual-gustatory (“I heard ‘I will harm you’ and at this very moment I saw blood dripping from my finger and it had the taste of blood when I put it on my tongue”), auditory-olfactory-tactile, auditory-olfactory-gustatory, auditory-tactile-gustatory, visual-olfactory-tactile, visual-olfactory-gustatory, visual-tactile-gustatory, olfactory-tactile-gustatory
(iv) 4-modal: auditory-visual-olfactory-tactile, auditory-visual-olfactory-gustatory, auditory-visual-tactile-gustatory (“I heard ‘I will harm you’ and then I saw blood dripping from my finger, while I felt a sharp pain there. It had the taste of blood when I put it on my tongue”), auditory-olfactory-tactile-gustatory, visual-olfactory-tactile-gustatory
At this step, it should be noted that multi-modal hallucinations retain their force from the plausibility that results from the simultaneous (or quasi-simultaneous) occurrence of two or more unimodal hallucinations of different types. For this reason, multi-modal hallucinations retain considerable power with regard to unimodal ones. The sense of reality that results from multi-modal hallucinations is due to the fact that several sensory pathways are congruently involved in the hallucinatory process. If we consider, for example, bimodal hallucinations of the auditory-visual type, it proves to be that the simultaneous occurrence of an additional visual hallucination strongly reinforces the sense of reality that results from the auditory hallucination. As the above examples illustrate, multi-modal hallucinations are seemingly highly more plausible and realistic than unimodal ones, and result in a much greater sense of realism. More generally, it illustrates how (n + 1)-modal hallucinations are seemingly much more realistic than n-modal ones, a supplementary sensory pathway being involved in the hallucinatory process.
1.2 Factors of plausibility of auditory hallucinations
It is worth mentioning, second, several factors that can contribute to the intrinsic plausibility of auditory hallucinations:
(i) structured versus unstructured auditory hallucinations: structured sounds notably consist of comments on the patient’s thoughts or activities, conversations of several persons, or commands ordering the patient to do things, etc., while on the other hand, unstructured sounds consist of ringing, buzzing, whistling, etc.
(ii) auditory hallucinations having an external versus an internal origin: auditory hallucinations seemingly coming out from outer space could reinforce the idea that the voices have an external origin, e.g. are attributable to other people.
(iii) the locus (Chadwick et al., 1996, p. 103) – i.e. the space location – of auditory hallucinations is also susceptible of reinforcing their intrinsic plausibility. We can consider, for example, a patient who hears the voice of the presenter of the show saying ‘Bastard!’. Now this sounds more realistic if the locus of the voice is the television device rather than the ashtray. Let us suppose now that the patient hears a voice saying ‘I can read your thoughts’. Now it sounds more likely to the patient if the voice comes out from the telephone than from the halogen lamp.
It is worth noting here that this criterion is susceptible to vary from culture to culture.1 In effect, depending on the individuals, a speaking tree or a speaking animal could be, in certain cases, consistent with the patient’s cultural background.
(iv) bilateral versus unilateral auditory hallucinations: auditory hallucinations coming indifferently from the patient’s right or from his/her left are more plausible than unilateral ones.2
(v) time location related versus unrelated to the patient’s thoughts, emotions or actions (Stephane et al. 2003 make mention of the “relation to the moment”). In this regard, auditory hallucinations that are simultaneous with the patients internal phenomena gain more plausibility.
(vi) phrases versus single words: in this context, phrases, conversations, elaborate sentences gain are more plausible than single words.
(vii) multiple voices versus single voice (Stephane et al., 2003).
(viii) auditory hallucinations fitting versus not fitting with the patient’s desires or fears: this factor consists of whether the hallucinations experienced by a patient fit adequately or not with his/her individual fears or desires. For in the affirmative, it would greatly increase the plausibility of the corresponding hallucinations. Let us take an example. The patient is very anxious about the evolution of his/her illness. He/she hears a voice that says: ‘You will relapse next month’. Now the content of this auditory hallucination fits adequately with the patient’s own fears. The reason why auditory hallucinations fitting with desires or fears are more plausible, is that they are coherent with the patient’s belief system. By contrast, had the content of auditory hallucinations been unrelated or contradictory with the patient’s desires and fears, the corresponding information would have then resulted in a lack of coherence with the patient’s belief system (this is in line with the approach to hallucinations exposed in Rector & Beck, 2002, which is concerned with: “(…) how the specific voice content and beliefs about the voices reflect the person’s prehallucinatory fears, concerns, interests, preoccupations and fantasies”).
(ix) interactive versus non-interactive voices: whether the patient can interact or not with voices, i.e. discuss or engage in dialog with them.
1.3 Factors of plausibility of visual hallucinations
Several factors can contribute, third, to the intrinsic plausibility of visual hallucinations:
(i) formed versus unformed visual hallucinations: formed hallucinations are made up of figures, faces, morphing objects or scenes. By contrast, unformed hallucinations consist of dots, lines, geometrical figures, flashes, etc.
(ii) ordinary versus bizarre or extraordinary visual hallucinations: for obvious reasons, objects that look ordinary gain more likeliness than bizarre, unreal objects.
(iii) objects in color versus in black and white.
(iv) visual hallucinations fitting versus not fitting with surroundings: as noted by Teunisse et al. (1996), the relationship to surroundings could play an important role in the plausibility of complex hallucinations. Such or such unimodal hallucination could fit well (e.g. a person lying on a bed, a scorpion walking on the ground) or not (a figure on the ceiling) with surroundings. Now it should be apparent that fitting with surroundings visual hallucinations are consistent with the patient’s knowledge of the physical world. This renders, from the patient’s viewpoint, the hallucination very plausible. By analogy with the locus of auditory hallucinations, fitting with surroundingscan be assimilated to the locus – i.e. space location – of visual hallucinations.
(v) bilateral versus unilateral visual hallucinations.
(vi) time location of visual hallucinations related versus unrelated to the patient’s thoughts, emotions or actions (e.g. the patient thinks to a scorpion and at this very moment he/she sees a scorpion on the ground).
(vii) animated versus static images.
1.4 Factors of plausibility of olfactory hallucinations
Several factors can contribute, fourth, to the plausibility of olfactory hallucinations:
(i) bilateral versus unilateral olfactory hallucinations.
(ii) olfactory hallucinations fitting versus not fitting with the patient’s desires or fears: the patient fears of being killed and smells a poisonous gas in his/her room.
(iii) transient versus permanent olfactory hallucinations: some patients experience olfactory hallucinations that occur any time of day and also last for hours (Tousi & Frankel 2004).
1.5 Factors of plausibility of tactile hallucinations
Certain factors can contribute, fifth, to the plausibility of tactile hallucinations:
(i) bilateral versus unilateral tactile hallucinations.
(ii) tactile hallucinations fitting versus not fitting with the patient’s desires or fears: the patient fears of being murdered and feels an electric-shock sensation.
1.6 Factors of plausibility of gustatory hallucinations
Some factors can contribute, sixth, to the plausibility of gustatory hallucinations:
(i) common versus strange gustatory hallucinations: in some cases, the patient may find that his/her food tastes strange. This could decrease the plausibility of the corresponding hallucination, in contrast with gustatory hallucinations where the patient experiences normal and common tastes.
(ii) gustatory hallucinations fitting versus not fitting with the patient’s desires or fears: the patient fears of being poisoned and feels the taste of poison in his/her mouth.
2. Plausibility of hallucinations scale
From the above, it results that it could be useful to measure accurately the plausibility of the hallucinations occurring in schizophrenia. For this purpose, we shall now sketch a 50-item scale, which is targeted at evaluating the plausibility of hallucinations experienced by a patient. This binary scale consists of a questionnaire which allows for yes/no answers (each yes answer weighting 2 points):
item
questions (0-100)
Unimodal hallucinations
Auditory hallucinations
1
Does the patient hear auditory hallucinatory which consist of structured sounds?
2
Does the patient experience auditory hallucinations which come out from outer space?
3
Does the patient experience auditory hallucinations whose locus sounds realistic?
4
Does the patient experience bilateral auditory hallucinations?
5
Does the patient experience auditory hallucinations whose time location is related to the patient’s thoughts, emotions or actions?
6
Does the patient experience auditory hallucinations which consist of phrases, conversations?
7
Does the patient experience auditory hallucinations with multiple voices?
8
Does the patient experience auditory hallucinations whose content fits with his/her fears or desires?
10
Can the patient interact with auditory hallucinations, i.e. discuss or engage in dialog with them?
Visual hallucinations
11
Does the patient experience formed visual hallucinations?
12
Does the patient experience visual hallucinations with ordinary objects?
13
Does the patient experience visual hallucinations in color?
14
Does the patient experience visual hallucinations whose locus fits with surroundings?
15
Does the patient experience bilateral visual hallucinations?
16
Does the patient experience visual hallucinations whose time location is related to his/her thoughts, emotions or actions?
17
Does the patient experience visual hallucinations consisting of scenes or sequences of animated images?
Olfactory hallucinations
18
Does the patient experience bilateral olfactory hallucinations?
19
Does the patient experience olfactory hallucinations whose content fits with his/her fears or desires?
20
Does the patient experience transient olfactory hallucinations?
Tactile hallucinations
21
Does the patient experience bilateral tactile hallucinations?
22
Does the patient experience tactile hallucinations whose content fits with his/her fears or desires?
Gustatory hallucinations
23
Does the patient experience gustatory hallucinations of a common type?
24
Does the patient experience gustatory hallucinations whose content fits with his/her fears or desires?
Bimodal hallucinations
25
Does the patient experience bimodal hallucinations of the auditory-visual type?
26
Does the patient experience bimodal hallucinations of the auditory-olfactory type?
27
Does the patient experience bimodal hallucinations of the auditory-tactile type?
28
Does the patient experience bimodal hallucinations of the auditory-gustatory type?
29
Does the patient experience bimodal hallucinations of the visual-olfactory type?
30
Does the patient experience bimodal hallucinations of the visual-tactile type?
31
Does the patient experience bimodal hallucinations of the visual-gustatory type?
32
Does the patient experience bimodal hallucinations of the olfactory-tactile type?
33
Does the patient experience bimodal hallucinations of the olfactory-gustatory type?
34
Does the patient experience bimodal hallucinations of the tactile-gustatory type?
Trimodal hallucinations
35
Does the patient experience trimodal hallucinations of the auditory-visual-olfactory type?
36
Does the patient experience trimodal hallucinations of the auditory-visual-tactile type?
37
Does the patient experience trimodal hallucinations of the auditory-visual-gustatory type?
38
Does the patient experience trimodal hallucinations of the auditory-olfactory-tactile type?
39
Does the patient experience trimodal hallucinations of the auditory-olfactory-gustatory type?
40
Does the patient experience trimodal hallucinations of the auditory-tactile-gustatory type?
41
Does the patient experience trimodal hallucinations of the visual-olfactory-tactile type?
42
Does the patient experience trimodal hallucinations of the visual-olfactory-gustatory type?
43
Does the patient experience trimodal hallucinations of the visual-tactile-gustatory type?
44
Does the patient experience trimodal hallucinations of the olfactory-tactile-gustatory type?
quadri-modal hallucinations
45
Does the patient experience quadri-modal hallucinations of the auditory-visual-olfactory-tactile type?
46
Does the patient experience quadri-modal hallucinations of the auditory-visual-olfactory-gustatory type?
47
Does the patient experience quadri-modal hallucinations of the auditory-visual-tactile-gustatory type?
48
Does the patient experience quadri-modal hallucinations of the auditory-olfactory-tactile-gustatory type?
49
Does the patient experience quadri-modal hallucinations of the visual-olfactory-tactile-gustatory type?
quinti-modal hallucinations
50
Does the patient experience quinti-modal hallucinations of the auditory-visual-tactile-olfactory-gustatory type?
It is worth noting that this 50-item scale can be regarded as non-specific to psychotic hallucinations. It is also suited to other disorders or illnesses involving hallucinations. Among these are other mental illnesses, but also Charles Bonnet syndrome (Teunisse et al., 1996; Menon et al., 2003), epilepsy (Sachdev, 1998; Schwartz & Marsh, 2000), etc. In particular, the Charles Bonnet syndrome occurs in the elderly and is usually associated with ocular pathology and severe visual impairment. The Charles Bonnet syndrome is characterized by the presence of complex and persistent visual hallucinations. The syndrome is usually associated with an absence of hallucinations in other sensory modalities. It is worth noting that the Charles Bonnet syndrome affects psychologically normal individuals with full or partial insight and the patients are accordingly non-delusional. On the other hand, auditory hallucinations are frequently associated with temporal lobe epilepsy, where hallucinations in other modalities can also occur.
It is worth mentioning that the Plausibility of Hallucinations Scale could also be used in association with other instruments for measuring insight, such as the Beck Cognitive Insight Scale (Beck et al., 2003) in order to gain more accurate knowledge of the patient’s state. For schizophrenia is usually associated with lack of insight into the internal origin of the hallucinations. By contrast, in other illnesses such as Charles Bonnet syndrome or in pseudo-hallucinations related to brain trauma or PTSD (Stephane et al., 2004), the patient usually retains insight into the internal origin of his/her hallucinations.
3. Impact on Cognitive Therapy
We suggest that the above emphasis on the plausibility of hallucinations could be usefully incorporated into the process of cognitive-behavior therapy of schizophrenia (Kingdon & Turkington, 1994, 2005; Chadwick et al., 1996; Rector & Beck, 2002). The general idea would be to point out to the patient who experiences highly plausible hallucinations those factors that confer to his/her hallucinations their intrinsic plausibility. Hopefully, this could insert itself well into the process of cognitive-behavior therapy, whose primary goal is to help the patient gaining more insight into the nature of his/her hallucinations and in particular to understand that they do not originate from an external source. In this context, stressing to the patient the plausibility of his/her hallucinations, could help him/her understand better how hallucinations can be self-deceiving.
It is worth focusing, to begin with, on multi-modal hallucinations. In this context, a first step would be to point out to the patient that multi-modal hallucinations are capable of seeming very plausible and realistic. It could then be argued and explained to the patient that multi-modal hallucinations are more plausible than unimodal ones. This could be illustrated through some examples. This latter strategy could make use of “what if statements” (Ellis & Dryden, 1997). Along these lines, it could be pointing out to the patient that if someone, instead of experiencing one single auditory hallucination, would experience simultaneously one supplementary visual hallucination, then the resulting multi-modal (of the auditory-visual type) hallucination would sound much more realistic. Along these lines, it could be pointed out to the patient that the particular case of multi-modal hallucination that he/she experiences is potentially very realistic and inherently capable of deceiving him/her.
Once the patient familiar with the concept of multi-modal hallucinations, another goal could be to learn the patient how to use by himself/herself the preceding taxonomy of multi-modal hallucinations and to apply it when he/she experiences these types of complex hallucinations. He/she would then be capable of identifying the corresponding case at hand. Hopefully, this could help the patient rationalize his/her abnormal perceptions and perhaps accept better the internal origin of his/her hallucinations as an alternative explanation.
The fact of classifying multi-modal hallucinations would be helpful to the patient, it seems, to help him/her rationalize and explain the phenomena he/she experiences. For we should bear in mind that the patient experiences abnormal phenomena, which are unfamiliar to psychologically normal people. In this context, helping the patient rationalize, classify and describe accurately the phenomena of his/her own internal world, proves then to be a valuable practical goal to attain. Accordingly, identifying, recognizing and labeling a given type of multi-modal hallucination could help lessen its associated omnipotence (Chadwick et al., 1996). This could be helpful to the patient, we suggest, who ordinarily faces an unexplained and upsetting phenomenon. More generally, the fact of identifying the various factors that render his/her complex hallucinations so plausible could help the patient gaining more insight into the internal origin of his/her hallucinations. At this step, it should be noted that the present account is notably in line – for what concerns the delusion that consists in attributing an external origin to the hallucinations – with the views advocated by Brendan Maher (1988, 1999), who sees delusions as a patient’s attempt to explain some perplexing and puzzling phenomena. According to Maher, delusions arise from normal (mainly rational but occasionally irrational) reasoning applied to abnormal phenomena. Among these abnormal phenomena which are very perplexing to the patient are the hallucinations.
4. Limitations and directions for further research
The main limitation of the present study is that the psychometric properties of the Plausibility of Hallucinations Scale have not been tested. However, given the number of items of the scale, one can expect a good sensibility. On the other hand, the reliability and validity of the scale remain to be tested.
Finally, the above developments suggest several questions, which could be usefully the subject of further study, based on the Plausibility of Hallucinations Scale. A first question that arises is the following: (i) Is the plausibility of hallucinations rate higher in schizophrenia than in other illnesses involving hallucinations, e.g. other mental illnesses, Charles Bonnet syndrome, temporal lobe epilepsy, etc.? A comparison of the plausibility of hallucinations rate occurring in schizophrenia and other illnesses involving hallucinations could be made accordingly. We suggest that such comparison could provide some useful information about the relationships of these illnesses (Sachdev, 1998). Although schizophrenia (paranoid subtype) should prima facie involve a higher rating, it seems that an accurate measure of the degree of plausibility of hallucinations could result in some interesting information. Along these lines, a comparison of the plausibility of hallucinations ratings occurring in different subtypes of schizophrenia could also be informative.
The above Plausibility of Hallucinations Scale is also designed to allow for comparisons between different chronological states in the same patient. This suggests a second type of question: (ii) Does the plausibility of hallucinations rating evolve during the course of schizophrenia? Along these lines, Nayani & David (1996) observed an increase in the complexity of auditory hallucinations over time, seemingly related to lesser distress and better coping. A similar question could be raised for other illnesses involving hallucinations. In this context, Menon et al. (2003) reported accordingly that “Elementary hallucinations may progressively evolve into complex visual hallucinations” in the Charles Bonnet syndrome.
Lastly, a third interesting question goes as follows: (iii) Is the plausibility rate of hallucinations occurring in schizophrenia correlated with the I.Q. of the patient, i.e. do patients with a high I.Q. more frequently experience complex hallucinations with a high level of plausibility? In other words, is the following hypothesis confirmed: The higher the I.Q., the higher the plausibility of hallucinations rating? Hopefully, the answer to these questions will provide some information that might well be useful to the understanding of the illness and to cognitive-behavior therapy of schizophrenia.
Acknowledgments
We thank Peter Brugger, Paul Gilbert and Hélène Verdoux for very useful comments on earlier drafts.
References
American Psychiatric Association (1994). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (4th edition). American Psychiatric Association: Washington.
Beck, A. T., Rector, N. A. (2003). A Cognitive Model of Hallucinations. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 27(1), 19-52.
Beck, A. T., Baruch, E., Balter, J. M., Steer, R. A., Warman, D. M. (2004). A new instrument for measuring insight: the Beck Cognitive Insight Scale. Schizophrenia Research, 68(2-3), 319-329.
Chadwick, P., Birchwood, M. & Trower, P. (1996). Cognitive Therapy for Delusions, Voices, and Paranoia. Chichester: Wiley.
Ellis, A., Dryden, W. (1997). The practice of rational emotive behaviour therapy, London: Free Association Books.
Kingdon, D. & Turkington, D. (1994). Cognitive-behavioural Therapy of Schizophrenia. Guilford: New York.
Kingdon, D., & Turkington, D. (2005). Cognitive Therapy of Schizophrenia. New York, London: Guilford.
Maher, B. A. (1988). Anomalous experiences and delusional thinking: the logic of explanations. In: T.F. Oltmanns & B.A. Maher (Eds.), Delusional Beliefs,pp. 15-33.Wiley: New York.
Maher, B. A. (1999). Anomalous experience in everyday life: Its significance for psychopathology. The Monist, 82, 547-570.
Menon, G. J., Rahman, I., Menon, S. J., Dutton, G. N. (2003). Complex visual hallucinations in the visually impaired: the Charles Bonnet Syndrome. Survey of Ophthalmology, 48, 58-72.
Nayani, T. H., David, A. S. (1996). The auditory hallucination: a phenomenological survey. Psychological Medicine, 26(1), 177-189.
Rector, N. A., Beck A. T. (2002). Cognitive Therapy for Schizophrenia: From Conceptualization to Intervention. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 47(1), 41-50.
Sachdev, P. (1998). Schizophrenia-Like Psychosis and Epilepsy: The Status of the Association. American Journal of Psychiatry, 155(3), 325-336.
Schwartz, J. M., Marsh, L. (2000). The Psychiatric Perspectives of Epilepsy. Psychosomatics, 41(1), 31-38.
Siddle, R. (2002). Communications from my parents. In: D. Kingdon & D. Turkington (Eds.), The Case Study Guide to Cognitive Behaviour Therapy of Psychosis, pp. 109-121. Chichester: Wiley.
Stephane, M., Thuras, P., Nasrallah, H., Georgopoulos, A. P. (2003). The internal structure of the phenomenology of auditory verbal hallucinations. Schizophrenia Research, 61, 185-193. Stephane, M., Hill, T., Matthew, E., & Folstein, M. (2004) New phenomenon of abnormal auditory perception associated with emotional and head trauma: Pathological confirmation by SPECT scan. Brain and Language, 89, 503-507.
Teunisse, R. J., Cruysberg, J. R., Hoefnagels, W. H. (1996). Visual hallucinations in psychologically normal people: Charles Bonnet’s syndrome. Lancet, 347, 794-797.
Toone, B. K. (2000). The psychoses of epilepsy. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and Psychiatry, 69(1), 1-3.
Tousi, B. & Frankel, M. (2004). Olfactory and visual hallucinations in Parkinson’s disease, Parkinsonism and Related Disorders, 10, 253-254.
1 We thank Paul Gilbert for the suggestion of taking into account cultural beliefs with regard to this specific criterion.
2 We owe the suggestion to include the bilateral/unilateral distinction related to hallucinations in all modalities to Peter Brugger.
English translation of a paper published in French in Philosophiques, autumn 2008, under the title “Une défense logique du modèle de Maher pour les délires polythématiques”.
In this paper, we proceed to describe a model for the formation and maintenance of polythematic delusions encountered in schizophrenia, which is in adequation with Brendan Maher’s account of delusions. Polythematic delusions are considered here as the conclusions of arguments triggered by apophenia that include some very common errors of reasoning such as post hoc fallacy and confirmation bias. We describe first the structure of reasoning which leads to delusions of reference, of telepathy and of influence, by distinguishing between the primary, secondary, tertiary and quaternary types of delusional arguments. These four levels of arguments correspond to a stage the nature of which is respectively instantial, inductive, interpretative at a monothematic level and interpretative at a polythematic level. We also proceed to identify accurately the fallacious steps in the corresponding reasoning. We expose then the role of apophenia in the elaboration of delusional ideas. Lastly, we describe the role played by the hallucinations in the present model.
This article is cited in:
How delusion is formed? Park J.S., Kang U.G., Medical Hypotheses, 24 Dec 2015, 87: pages 61-65
A Logical Defence of Maher’s Model of Polythematic Delusions
Paul FRANCESCHI
Classically, the term of “delusion” applies to two fundamentally distinct forms: monothematic and polythematic delusions (Davies & Coltheart 2000; Bortolotti 2005). Monothematic delusions present an unique topic and are usually associated with cerebral lesions. Among the latter, one can mention Capgras’ delusion (by virtue of which the patient thinks that one of his/her fellows has been replaced by an impostor), Fregoli’s delusion (when the patient is persuaded that he/she is followed by one or several persons whom he cannot identify because they are dressed up) or Cotard’s delusion (when the patient is persuaded that he/she is died). Conversely, polythematic delusions have numerous topics, which are most often interconnected and usually linked to psychotic disturbances. Among polythematic delusions, one can notably mention: delusion of reference, delusion of grandeur, delusion of influence, delusion of persecution, delusion of control, delusion of telepathy.
In what follows, I will set out to introduce a new, as far as I know, model of the mechanism which leads to the formation of polythematic delusionsi met in schizophrenia. This model, which takes place in the recent development of psycho-pathological philosophy (Faucher, 2006), offers to describe the mechanism which leads, on the one hand, to the formation of delusional ideas and on the other hand, to their maintenance. In this model, delusions are the result of the patient’s cognitive activity in response to a specific form of abnormal perception. Even though the corresponding reasoning appears essentially normal, it includes however the repetition of some typical errors of reasoning. This leads to consider polythematic delusions as the conclusions of fallacious arguments, worked out in response to a particular type of abnormal perception, among which one can distinguish between primary, secondary, tertiary and quaternary delusional arguments. These four levels of arguments correspond, as we shall see it, to some functional stages the nature of which is respectively instantial (based on several instances), inductive (generalising the conclusion of each of the instances), interpretative at a monothematic level and finally, interpretative at a polythematic level.
It is worth mentioning, moreover, that the notion of delusion has important philosophical underpinnings. In particular, the understanding of delusions proves to be essential for the notions of belief (Engel 2001, Bayne & Pacherie 2005), of justification of beliefs, of knowledge, of rationality (Campbell 2001, Bortolotti 2005) and also of self-deception.
1. Cognitive models of delusions
Edvard Munch: The Scream.
Before describing in detail the present model, it is worth presenting the main cognitive models for delusions encountered in the literature. Some authors described then a cognitive model for delusional ideas observed in schizophrenia. As Chadwick & al. (1996) underline it, as well as Fowler & al. (1995) who set out to review these types of models, there does not truly exist a unique cognitive model for delusions, for it rather consists of a family of models.
A first cognitive model was described by Chadwick & al. (1996), who set out to introduce an application to delusions of Albert Ellis’ ABC-analysis. The original model described by Ellis (1962) consists of a diagram which plays a preponderant role in the emergence of mental disorders. Ellis distinguishes thus between three types of events: A, B and C. The As (for Activating event) are external facts or events of the patient’s internal life, such as thoughts or bodily feelings. The Bs (for Belief) are thoughts relating to the same events, which themselves are possibly rational in nature or not. Moreover, the corresponding cognitive process can be more or less conscious. Finally, the Cs (for Consequence) are emotional states such as anger, sadness, joy, frustration, etc. which can be of a positive or negative nature. Thus, the Cs that follow irrational thoughts are most often of a negative nature. The succession of events of type A, B and C plays a predominant role in the emergence of mental disorders: activating events trigger irrational thoughts, which themselves engender negative emotions. The type of therapy recommended by Ellis consists precisely in rendering the patient aware of this mechanism and in controlling the corresponding process. Adapting Ellis’ original model to psychosis, Chadwick & al. point out thus how the As constitute events that are external or internal to the patient, the Bs are his/her thoughts and the Cs are constituted by the emotions triggered by the patient’s thoughts. This specific framework allows to provide a cognitive ABC-analysis of the main types of delusions. For example, the delusion of persecution finds its origin in the external fact that the patient hears the noise of a car’s horn; this triggers in the patient the thought according to which his/her enemies come to kill him/her; it follows then in the patient’s a negative emotion of fright and of anxiety.
A second cognitive model of delusions was put forth by Brendan Maher (1974; 1988; 1999). Maher did suggest that delusions are the result – in the context of schizophrenia of paranoid subtype – of a broadly normal interpretation of the abnormal phenomena undergone by the patient (hallucinations, loss of audition, impairment in the intensity of perception, etc.). According to Maher, it is not therefore by his/her reasoning that the patient differs from a normal individual, but by his/her own altered perceptions. Delusional ideas are thus conceived of as a response to abnormal and emotionally disturbing phenomena experienced by the patient. Such disturbing phenomena lead the patient to search an explanation, which is at the origin of the delusional construction. According to Maher, the patient’s intellectual process is a product of normal reasoning and does not differ significantly from the one which is shown in every individual, or even in every scientist, when confronted with an unexplained phenomenon: “It is the core of the present hypothesis that the explanations (i.e. the delusions) of the patient are derived by cognitive activity that is essentially indistinguishable from that employed by non-patients, by scientists and by people generally.” (Maher 1974, 103). By normal reasoning, Maher means here a basically logical reasoning, but which occasionally includes some errors of reasoning of a common type. It is worth mentioning here that Maher’s model has led to several objections. Above all, this model was criticised on the grounds that it did not allow to account for the fact that delusions can also develop in seemingly normal conditions (Chapman & Chapman 1988). Secondly, it was objected to Maher’s model (Davies & Coltheart 2000, p. 8) that it did not explain how delusional beliefs are adopted and maintained in spite of their implausible nature. It is worth mentioning lastly that an important philosophical problem emerges within Maher’s model. It is what Pascal Engel termed the “paradox of delusions” (Engel 2001), and that can be formulated as follows: if the delusional construction is underlain by essentially normal reasoning and therefore by rationality, how it is possible to explain that the delusions’ conclusions are so manifestly wrong and contrary to evidence. The present analysis takes place in such context, and aims thus at proposing a solution to this paradox of delusions.
While Maher’s conception mentions abnormal perception as a unique factor at the origin of delusional ideas, another approach, notably put forth by Martin Davies and Max Coltheart (2000, 2001), describe two factors in the genesis and the maintenance of delusions. The first factor resides, as well as for Maher, in abnormal perception. And the second factor resides, according to Davies and Coltheart, in the patient’s disability to reject a hypothesis given its incoherent and implausible nature with regard to the patient’s rest of knowledge. Davies and Coltheart criticises thus Maher’s model by notably pointing out that it does not allow to provide an account of the maintenance of delusions, even though their conclusion turns out to be completely implausible.
It is worth also mentioning a third type of cognitive model, which stresses that several cognitive biases (Garety & al. 2001) can be observed in the thinking mode of patients suffering from schizophrenia. Among these biases is the patient’s tendency to jump-to-conclusions (Garety & Hemsley 1994). Experimental studies (Fear & Healy 1997; Garety & al. 1991) showed thus that patients had a more marked tendency than others to conclude very fast, starting from a limited group of information at their disposal. A second type of cognitive bias is an attribution or externalist bias which consists for the patient to attribute an external motive to events of a negative type which he/she undergoes. The patient favours then arbitrarily an external reason with regard to an internal and personal motive, when he/she sets out to determine the origin of an event which relates to him/her. Such conclusion notably results from the work of Bentall & Kaney (1989), and Kaney & al. (1989), who noticed that patients suffering from delusions of persecution were more prone than normal individuals to attribute both an external cause to negative events which they undergo and an internal motive to positive events which concerned them. This type of cognitive bias is also related to an attentional bias, which was noticed (Bentall & al. 1989; Kaney & al. 1989) in patients suffering from schizophrenia of paranoid subtype, who demonstrate as well a more marked tendency than others to turn their attention to menacing elements, among a group of stimuli, especially if the latter are related with themselves. Lastly, Aaron Beck (2002) also underlined how the reasoning of patients suffering from schizophrenia revealed an egocentric bias. This type of cognitive bias leads the patient to relate most external events with the elements of his/her personal life. Noise, sounds, smells, and generally facts and external phenomena, are thus bearing for the patient a hidden or explicit meaning, and which concerns him/her directly.
Finally, it is worth mentioning a cognitive model which sets out to define accurately the nature of delusions, by especially emphasising the fact that the latter do not constitute beliefs in the usual sense or, possibly, constitute beliefs of a special type. Such model made the subject of recent developments (Sass,1994; Young, 1999; Engel, 2001; Stephens & Graham, 2006) tending to question the classical definition of delusions, based on abnormal belief.
2. Apophenia
I will now endeavour to describe the present model and to expose accurately the mechanism which leads to the formation and maintenance of delusional ideas. In Maher’s model, delusions constitute a cognitive development elaborated by the patient in response to abnormal perception. The present model inserts itself within such conception: polythematic delusions constitute then conclusions of fallacious arguments worked out by the patient, in response to a particular type of abnormal perception: apophenia. Finally, although the reasoning which leads to delusions proves to be fallacious, it can however be considered as normal, because it includes errors of reasoning which turn out to be very common.
Before describing the structure of reasoning which leads to polythematic delusions, it is worth considering preliminarily the apophenia. One finds then mention, especially in the observations made by some patients in remission relating their psychotic experience (Stanton & David 2000), of a very specific feeling, which can be characterised as a feeling of interconnection with the ambient world. Such feeling is not felt in normal conditions and truly presents a bizarre nature. Schneider had already (1930) pointed out how in an individual suffering from schizophrenia, a meaningful interconnection was created between facts that are internal to the patient and external events (“Meaningful connections are created between temporary coincident external impressions … or perceptions with thoughts that happen to be present, or events and recollections happening to occur in consciousness at the same time”). Isabel Clarke (2000) also mentions in the patient a very particular feeling of fusion and of universal interconnection (“an exhilarating feeling of unity and interconnectedness”). Brundage (1983) also evokes a phenomenon of the same nature which manifests itself by a particular feeling of connection with all events that occur in the surroundings (“there is a connection to everything that happens”) as well as the feeling that the slightest things have a meaning (“every single thing means something”). It appears then that the patient experiences a strong feeling of interconnection between on the one hand, his/her internal phenomena and on the other hand, the external phenomena.
The role of such feeling of interconnection was recently underlined notably by Peter Brugger (2001). Brugger terms then apophenia the tendency to see connections between objects or ideas which are a priori without any relationship (“the propensity to see connections between seemingly unrelated objects or ideas”) and attributes the creation of this term to K. Conrad (1958). In the present context, one can consider a slightly more restrictive definition of apophenia, for it suffices here to characterise apophenia as the feeling in the patient that there is a narrow relationship between his/her internal phenomena (thought, feelings, emotions, acts) and external phenomena.
One can notice here that Maher does not mention explicitly apophenia when he enumerates abnormal perceptions which are susceptible of being experienced by the patient. However, he mentions a phenomenon which appears as closely related to apophenia. Among the abnormal perceptions undergone by the patient, Maher mentions indeed (Maher 1999) that it can consist, for example, of the fact that the patient perceives as salient some normally insignificant sensory data, of unrecognised defects in the sensory system of the patient such as a loss of audition, of temporary impairments in the intensity of perception, of hallucinations, of difficulties of concentration of neurological origin, etc. Maher includes then among abnormal perceptions the fact that the patient perceives as salient some ordinarily insignificant sensory data, what can be considered as closely related to apophenia.
At this step, it is worth describing more accurately the cognitive mechanism which, in relation with apophenia, leads to the formation of polythematic delusions. This will allow to cast more light on the role and the nature of apophenia itself.
3. Formation and maintenance of delusional ideas
In the present context, the reasoning that leads to delusional ideas is considered as a specific case of fallacious argument, i.e. as reasoning the conclusion of which is not logically justified by its premises, which are worked out in response to a particular type of abnormal perception: apophenia. In general, this type of reasoning leads to an erroneous conclusion. But it can happen very exceptionally that the resulting conclusion turns out to be true (for example if a patient suffering from schizophrenia with delusion of persecution was mistakenly spied on notably because he/she had been confused with a high diplomat). Another feature of the type of fallacious reasoning which leads to polythematic delusions is that it includes errors of reasoning of a normal type, i.e. very common. Finally, it is worth pointing out that in spite of their patently false conclusion, the task which consists in diagnosing accurately the fallacious steps in the reasoning which leads to delusional ideas proves to be far from easy.
The fallacious reasoning which leads to polythematic delusions presents a particular structure, as we will see it, within which it is worth distinguishing several functional steps, which take place successively within the elaboration of delusions ideas: primary, secondary, tertiary and quaternary steps. The primary step, first, is of an instantial nature, in the sense that it is based on some instances. The secondary step presents an inductive nature, which proceeds by generalisation of the conclusions resulting from each of the preceding instances. And the tertiary step is of an interpretative nature at a monothematic level. Finally, the quaternary step has an interpretative function, but this time at a polythematic level. The distinction of these four successive steps is of interest in the understanding of the mechanism which leads to the formation of delusional ideas, for it allows to describe its intrinsic structure, at the level of both its formation and maintenance. On the other hand, as we shall see it later, cognitive therapy of psychosis can apply differently to each of these specific steps.
In what follows, we shall especially be concerned with delusional ideas of reference, of telepathy, of influence and of grandeur, which correspond to polythematic delusions commonly met in schizophrenia. It is also worth mentioning that the corresponding model can be easily extended to other types of delusional ideas, especially to thought-broadcasting delusions or delusions of persecution. At this stage, it worth drawing a distinction between the mechanism which leads to the formation of delusional ideas, and the one which concurs to their maintenance.
3.1 Formation of delusional ideas
Classically, one distinguishes in schizophrenia the following types of delusions: delusion of reference, delusion of influence, delusion of control, delusion of telepathy, delusion of grandeur, delusion of persecution. The present model will set out first to describe the mechanism which leads to the formation of these main types of delusions, by setting out to introduce a reconstruction of the specific cognitive process in a patient at the beginning of psychosis.
Let us begin with delusions of reference. Let us consider the following argument, which leads the patient to conclude that television speaks about him/her, and therefore to delusional ideas of reference (T1 and T2 denote here two successive temporal positions, with a very short time interval between T1 and T2; the symbol denotes the conclusion; and R is taken for reference):
(R1) in T1 I was drinking an aperitif
(R2) in T2 the presenter of the show said: “Stop drinking!”
(R3) ∴ in T2 the presenter said: “Stop drinking!” because in T1 I was drinking an aperitif
(R4) in T3 I was upset and anxious
(R5) in T4 the presenter of the show said “Stop stressing”
(R6) ∴ in T4 the presenter of the show said “Stop stressing!” because in T3 I was upset and anxious
(R7) in T5 I was smoking a cigarette
(R8) in T6 I heard the presenter saying “That is not good !“
(R9) ∴ in T6 the presenter said “That is not good !” because in T5 I was smoking a cigarette
(R10) in T7 I felt fine and lucid and I was relaxed
(R11) in T8 the presenter of the show said: “We are in great form!
(R12) ∴ in T8 the presenter said “We are in great form!” because in T7 I felt fine and lucid and I was relaxed
(R…) …
(R13) ∴ the presenters of the shows speak according to what I do or what I feel
(R14) ∴ television speaks about me
One can distinguish within the structure of this reasoning several parts the function of which turns out to be specific. These different parts correspond respectively to primary delusional arguments (it consists of the steps (R1)-(R3), (R4)-(R6), (R7)-(R9) and (R10)-(R12)), to secondary delusional arguments (the steps (R3), (R6), (R9), (R12) and (R13)) and tertiary delusional arguments (the steps (R13) and (R14)). It is worth considering in turn each of these arguments. Let us begin with primary delusional arguments, that correspond to an instantial step, in the sense that it is made up of several different instances. Primary delusional arguments are constituted here by four different instances, i.e. the steps (R1)-(R3), (R4)-(R6), (R7)-(R9) and (R10)-(R12). These four primary delusional arguments lead the patient to conclude that at a given time, the TV presenters spoke according to his/her acts or to what he/she felt.
Let us consider now the following stage (R13), which constitutes the conclusion of a secondary delusional argument, and is of a different nature. Its premises are the conclusion (R3), (R6), (R9), (R12) of the four previous instances of primary delusional arguments of reference. The patient generalises from the latter to the conclusion that the TV presenters speak according to what he/she is doing or to what he/she is feeling. The overall structure of this type of secondary delusional argument is then as follows:
(R3) in T2 the presenter of the show spoke according to what I was doing
(R6) in T4 the presenter of the show spoke according to what I was feeling
(R9) in T6 the presenter of the show spoke according to what I was doing
(R12) in T8 the presenter of the show spoke according to what I felt
(R…) …
(R13) ∴ the presenters of the shows speak according to what I do or feel
On can then term inductive this type of secondary delusional argument because it has the form of an enumerative induction, where the patient constructs his/her conclusion by generalising, in an inductive way, from the conclusions of several instances of primary delusional arguments. Thus, secondary delusional arguments correspond to a step the nature of which proves to be inductive.
At this stage, it is also worth mentioning the third step, which leads to delusion of reference. It consists of the tertiary delusional argument of reference, constituted by steps (R13) and (R14), the premise (R13) of which being the conclusion of the secondary delusional argument of reference:
(R13) ∴ the presenters of the shows speak according to what I do or feel
(R14) ∴ television speaks about me
In such argument, the patient takes into account the conclusion of the inductive step that the presenters of the shows speak according to his/her acts or to his/her internal state, and interprets it by concluding that television speaks about him/her. It consists, as we did see it, of a step the function of which is merely interpretative, in the sense that it aims at making sense of the inductive conclusion which results from the secondary delusional argument. Tertiary delusional arguments are therefore the product of an interpretative step, which situates itself at a monothematic level (here, the specific topic is that of delusion of reference).
A structurally identical mechanism leads to delusional ideas of telepathy. Several instances of primary delusional arguments of influence lead first the patient to conclude that his/her own thoughts are at the origin of acts that are accomplished by other persons. By an inductive step, the patient is then led to the conclusion that people act according to his/her thoughts. Finally, in an interpretative step, the patient concludes that other people can read his/her thoughts (or that they can hear them). It consists there, in the patient’s mind, of an attempt at explaining the very disturbing conclusion which results from the inductive step according to which other persons act according to his/her thoughts.
The same mechanism also engenders the formation of delusional ideas of influence. In that case, several instances of primary delusional arguments of influence lead the patient to conclude that his/her own thoughts are at the origin of annoyances caused to other persons. An inductive step leads then the patient to the conclusion that people react negatively in function of his/her thoughts. Finally, an interpretative step leads the patient to conclude that he/she perturbs and disturbs other people.
Moreover, such mechanism leads to the formation of delusional ideas of control. They find their origin in the instances of primary delusional arguments of control. Such instances have the same structure as that of the instances of primary delusional arguments of reference, of telepathy or of influence, with however this difference that the temporal order of both types of events – internal and external, with regard to the patient – is now reversed. Within the primary delusional arguments of reference, of telepathy or of influence, an internal event with regard to the patient precedes an external event, whereas it is the opposite with regard to a primary delusional argument of control: the external event precedes then the internal event. Thus, several instances of primary delusional arguments of control lead the patient to conclude inductively that some external events have an effect on his/her thoughts, his/her emotions or his/her acts. The interpretative step leads then the patient to think that he/she is controlled by external beings or objects such as robots or a satellite.
Finally, it is worth specifying the role played by quaternary delusional arguments. The premises of the latter arguments are conclusions of tertiary delusional arguments. Quaternary delusional arguments are more general arguments, which present, as well as tertiary delusional arguments, an interpretative nature. But unlike tertiary delusional arguments which turn out to be interpretative at a monothematic level, quaternary delusional arguments are interpretative at a polythematic level. They indeed take into account jointly the conclusions of tertiary delusional arguments of reference, of telepathy, of influence, etc. by striving to make sense, globally,of them and to interpret them. The reasoning below constitutes then a quaternary delusional argument leading to ideas of grandeur:
(R15) television and the media speak about me
(T16) people can read my thoughts
(I17) I influence other people’s behaviour
(18) ∴ I am someone exceptional
(19) ∴ I am an extraterrestrial
At a quaternary level, the patient takes then into account the different conclusions resulting from tertiary delusional arguments, the function of which is interpretative at the level of a given delusional topic and attempts this time to interpret the set constituted by the latter. The resulting conclusion constitutes veritably, for the patient, an overall theory the function of which is to make sense and to explain all the abnormal phenomena which he/she experiences.
3.2 Maintenance of delusional ideas
It is worth considering now the mechanism which leads to the maintenance of delusional ideas. Let us place ourselves at the level of secondary delusional arguments which, at the level of the formation of delusional ideas, are of an inductive nature. Consider then especially the form that take secondary delusional arguments of reference, at the stage of the maintenance. At this step, the conclusion (R13) which results from secondary delusional arguments, in virtue of which the presenters of the shows speak according to what the patient makes or feels, was already established at the stage of the formation of delusional ideas. And the corresponding reasoning takes then into account a new instance of primary delusional argument (R20) of reference, in the following way:
(R20) in T100 the presenter of the show spoke according to what I was doing
(R21) ∴ this confirms that television speaks according to what I do
On can notice here that the inductive generalisation (R13) was already established at the stage of the formation of the secondary delusional argument, and that the new instance of primary delusional argument constitutes then, in the patient’s mind, a case of confirmation of the latter generalisation. As we can see, the role of the new instance of primary delusional argument is to confirm and therefore to reinforce, at the stage of the maintenance, a generalisation which was already established at the previous stage of the formation of delusional ideas.
4. Analysis of delusional arguments
At this stage, it is worth analysing in detail the structure of the type of reasoning which has been just described, in order to identify accurately the fallacious steps and to determine the role played by apophenia. Let us consider in turn primary, secondary, tertiary and quaternary delusional arguments. Let us scrutinise first the following instance of primary delusional argument of telepathy, which manifests itself at the level of the formation of delusions:
(T1) in T1 I thought of Michael “What an idiot!”
(T2) in T2 I heard Michael shout
(T3) ∴ in T2 I heard Michael shout because in T1 I thought of him “What an idiot!”
It appears here that the two premises (T1) and (T2) constitute genuine facts and therefore turn out to be true. Conversely, the conclusion (T3) that concludes to the existence of a relation of causality between the two consecutive facts F1 (in T1 I thought of Michael “What an idiot!”) and F2 (in T2 I heard Michael shout) is it justified? It appears not. Indeed, both premises are only establishing a relation of anteriority between the two consecutive facts F1 and F2. And the conclusion (T3) which deducts from it a causality relationship turns out therefore to be too strong. The corresponding reasoning presents then a fallacious nature. The corresponding error of reasoning, which concludes to a relation of causality while there is only a simple relation of anteriority, is traditionally called post hoc fallacy, according to the Latin sentence “Post hoc, ergo propter hoc” (thereafter, hence because of it). This is a very common type of fallacious reasoning, which is notably at the root of many superstitions (Martin 1998; Bressan 2002). David Hemsley (1992) notably mentions such type of reasoning in clinical observation: “A patient of the present author, recalling his psychotic experiences noted that the co-occurrence of two events often led immediately to an assumption of a causal relationship between them”. Finally, one can notice that in the context of cognitive distortions, the type of error of reasoning corresponding to post hoc fallacy can be considered a specific case of arbitrary inference.
Let us also proceed to analyse the type of reasoning which underlies secondary delusional arguments, and that presents at the stage of the formation of delusional ideas, as we did see it, the following inductive structure:
(T22) in T2 Michael spoke according to my thoughts
(T23) in T4 the neighbour spoke according to my thoughts
(T24) in T6 the radio presenter spoke according to my thoughts
(…)
(T25) ∴ people act according to my thoughts
Such type of reasoning appears prima facie completely correct. It consists here of a reasoning based on an inductive generalisation, in which the patient simply builds a more general conclusion from several instances. Such reasoning is completely correct, for its conclusion can be considered as true, inasmuch as its premises are true. However, a scrutiny reveals that the patient only takes into account here a limited number of instances, i.e. those instances that are based on the concordance of both premises, at the stage of primary delusional arguments. The patient then directs his/her attention exclusively to those instances that include two premises of which the internal event (premise 1) and the external event (premise 2) turn out to be concordant and render thus plausible a relation of causality. The corresponding turn of mind can be described as a concordance bias. In effect, the patient does not take into account at this stage those instances which could possibly be composed of two discordant premises. The latter are likely to come under two different forms. An instance of the first form is as follows:
(T1) in T1 I thought of Michael “What an idiot!”
(26) in T2 Michel was quiet
And an instance of the second form is :
(27) in T1 I didn’t think of Michael
(T2) in T2 I heard Michael shout
In these two types of cases, one can notice a discordance between the two premises, which goes directly contrary to the idea of causality between the two events. As we see it finally, the flaw in the patient’s reasoning resides essentially in the fact of only taking into account those instances where the concordance between an internal event and an external event renders plausible a causality relationship. But if the patient had taken into account at the same time the concordant and the discordant instances, he/she would have been led to conclude that the concordant instances represent only a small part of the set constituted by the class of relevant instances, and are only therefore the result of a random process. In such context, as we see it, the concordant instances in fact constitute but mere coincidences.
If one places oneself now at the stage of the maintenance of delusional ideas, one can observe the presence of a mechanism of the same nature. At the stage of the emergence of delusional ideas, secondary delusional arguments present, as we did see it, an inductive nature. On the other hand, at the stage of the maintenance of delusional ideas, the latter come under the form of arguments which lead to the confirmation of an inductive generalisation. Consider then the following instance, where the conclusion (T25) according to which people act according to the patient’s thoughts results from a secondary delusional argument and was already established at the stage of the formation of delusional ideas:
(T28) in T100 my sister spoke according to my thoughts
(T29) ∴ this confirms that people act according to my thoughts
This type of argument appears completely valid, for the conclusion results directly from its premises. However, the latter argument is also at fault by default, for it does not take into account some premises, which turn out to be as much as relevant as the instance (T28). As we can see, the error of reasoning consists then in taking only into account those instances which confirm the generalisation (T25), while ignoring those instances which disconfirm the latter. Hence, this type of argument reveals a confirmation bias, i.e. a tendency to favour those instances which confirm a generalisation, whereas it would be necessary to take into consideration at the same time those which confirm and those which disconfirm it. One can notice however that such type of cognitive bias presents a very common nature (Nickerson 1998, Jonas et al. 2001).
It is worth considering, third, tertiary delusional arguments. Consider then the following tertiary delusional argument of telepathy (a similar analysis also applies to tertiary delusional arguments of reference and of influence):
(T30) ∴ people act in function of my thoughts
(T31) ∴ people can read my thoughts (people can hear my thoughts)
One can notice here that if premise (T30) is true, then the conclusion (T31) constitutes a credible explanation. This type of argument presents then an interpretative nature and the conclusion (T31) according to which people can read the patient’s thoughts appears finally plausible, inasmuch as it is considered as true that people act according to his/her thoughts. As we can see, such argument is motivated by the patient’s concern of explaining and of interpreting the disturbing generalisation which results from the repetition of the many concordant above-mentioned instances.
Finally, the following quaternary delusional argument aims, in the same way, at making sense of the conclusions which result from the conjunction of conclusions of different tertiary delusional argument:
(R15) television and the media speak about me
(T16) people can read my thoughts
(I17) I influence people’s behaviour
(18) ∴ I am someone exceptional
(19) ∴ I am an extraterrestrial
As we can see it, the conclusion (18) results here directly from the three premises (R15), (T16) and (I17) and the corresponding reasoning which leads the patient to conclude that he/she is someone exceptional can also be considered as valid. On the other hand, the conclusion (19) appears here too strong with regard to premise (18).
Given what precedes, it appears that a number of steps in the reasoning which leads to delusional ideas in schizophrenia are characterised by a reasoning which appears mainly normal. By normal reasoning, one intends here a broadly logical and rational reasoning, but also including some errors of logic of a very common type. Such viewpoint corresponds to the one put forth by Maher (1988; 1999) who considers, as we did see it, that the delusional construction in schizophrenia is nothing else than normal reasoning worked out by the patient to try to explain the abnormal phenomena which he/she experiences.
However, one can notice that in the above-mentioned structure of reasoning, one part of the reasoning cannot a priori be truly considered as normal. It consists here of the different instances of primary delusional arguments. The latter are based, as we did see it, on errors of reasoning corresponding to post hoc fallacies. This type of error of reasoning arguably turns out to be extremely common. However, the instances of primary delusional arguments mentioned above present an unusual nature, in the sense that they put in relationship the patient’s thoughts (or his/her emotions, feelings or actions) with external phenomena. Prima facie, such type of reasoning cannot be considered as normal. For why is the patient led to put his/her thoughts in relationship with external phenomena? One can formulate the question more generally as follows: why does the patient put in relationship the phenomena of his/her internal and personal life (his/her thoughts, emotions, feelings, etc.) with mere external phenomena? This distinguishes itself indeed significantly from the behaviour of a normal person, for whom it exists a very clear-cut intuitive separation between on one hand, his/her own internal world, and on the other hand, the external phenomena.
The answer to the previous question can be found here in the role of apophenia. Due to apophenia, the feeling indeed imposes itself to the patient that his/her internal world is closely linked up with the external world. So, his/her thoughts, emotions, feelings and acts appear to him/her to be closely linked up with the external phenomena that he/she perceives, such as ambient noise and dialogues, the words of the presenters of television or of radio, the dialogues of the characters of comic strips, the movements of the wings of a butterfly or of a bird, the natural phenomena such as the wind or the rain, etc. In the context which results from apophenia, the repeated instances that constitute primary delusional arguments can then take place naturally. For since the patient lives with a permanent feeling of interconnection between events that relate to him/her specifically and those which occur in the world which surrounds him, he/she is then led to observe many concordances between events related to him/her and external facts. In such context, primary delusional arguments can then take place naturally.
In the present context, the role of apophenia can be considered as fundamental. And this leads to suggest that considering its specificity and considering the leading role that it plays in the development of primary delusional arguments and therefore of all the characteristic delusional ideas of schizophrenia, apophenia could be counted among the criteria of the illnessii.
As we can see it, the process which gives rise to delusional arguments from the phenomenological experience constituted by apophenia proves finally to be in line with Maher’s account. And one finds here a clear explanation of delusions as the patient’s response to the abnormal phenomena which he/she experiences, among which one can then mention apophenia, as well as hallucinations.
Given what precedes, polythematic delusions can be defined as conclusions of arguments triggered by apophenia and that include some very common errors of reasoning such as post hoc fallacy and confirmation bias. Hence, apophenia and a normal reasoning including the type of aforementioned errors of reasoning turn out to be necessary and sufficient conditions for the development of polythematic delusions. This double condition notably explains why we are not all delusional. For if errors in reasoning based on post hoc fallacy and confirmation bias turn out indeed to be very common, they only trigger primary delusional arguments when they are associated with the abnormal perception which consists in apophenia. It is worth pointing out, moreover, that such model leaves also room for more stronger conditions. For if apophenia constitutes one of the two sufficient conditions for the development of polythematic delusions, the latter can also take place in conditions where abnormal perception is constituted not only by apophenia, but also by other abnormal perceptions such as hallucinations. And also, whereas the second condition which is sufficient for delusions identifies itself with normal reasoning including post hoc fallacy and confirmation bias, it proves that the development of delusions can also be made by means of a reasoning which deviates more or less from normal reasoning. But the essential characteristic of the present model resides in the fact that apophenia and normal reasoning including the aforementioned very common errors, constitute necessary and sufficient conditions for the development of polythematic delusions.
5. The role of the hallucinations
At this stage, it is worth highlighting the role played by hallucinations, the other major symptom of schizophrenia, in the process which has just been described. I will set out to describe in more detail here the role played by auditory hallucinations – given that the corresponding analysis can be easily extended to hallucinations relating to other sensory modalities, i.e. visual, tactile, olfactory and gustatory.
Auditory hallucinations are susceptible, first, of playing a role at the level of primary delusional arguments. In this type of case, the primary delusional argument presents the same structure as the one described above, with the only difference that an auditory hallucination – in place of a real external event – constitutes then the second premise of the primary delusional argument. The following instance constitutes then an example of primary delusional argument of reference, but it is there an auditory hallucination, by which the patient hears the voice of the presenter of the show saying “Clumsy!” while he/she watches TV, that constitutes the support of the second premise of the argument:
(32) in T1 I dropped my pen
(33) in T2 I heard the voice of the presenter of the show saying “Clumsy!”
(34) ∴ in T2 the presenter of the show said “Clumsy!” because in T1 I dropped my pen
In the same way, the following instance constitutes a case of primary delusional argument of telepathy. In that case, it is an auditory hallucination, by which the patient hears the voice of his neighbour saying “Calm down!”, that serves as a basis for the second premise of the argument:
(35) in T1 I was very upset
(36) in T2 I heard the voice of my neighbour saying “Calm down!”
(37) ∴ in T2 my neighbour said “Calm down!” because in T1 I was very upset
It is worth mentioning, second, the role that can be played by auditory hallucinations at the level of secondary delusional arguments. In such case, the corresponding generalisations develop from instances of primary delusional arguments which also include auditory hallucinations. In the example below, the patient generalises from the conclusions of three instances of primary delusional arguments of reference. But while the two latter instances (39) and (40) are based on real external phenomena, the first instance (38) is founded on hallucinated content, by which the patient heard the TV presenter saying “Clumsy!”:
(38) in T2 the TV presenter said “Clumsy!” because in T1 I dropped my pen
(39) in T4 the presenteress said “Calm down!” because in T3 I was upset
(40) in T6 the presenter of the show said “Thank you” because in T5 I thought “I love this presenter”
(…) …
(41) ∴ the TV presenters speak according to what I do or feel
As we see it, auditory hallucinations contribute in this way to increase the number of primary delusional arguments, by creating thus additional instances which add up themselves to the different types of standard instances previously defined. This gives then more weight to the inductive generalisations made by the patient from multiple instances of primary delusional arguments. Besides, it has also the effect of reinforcing the coherence of the patient’s delusional system and of rendering it then more resistant to contrary argumentation.
It is worth mentioning, lastly, another type of role which can be played by auditory hallucinations. Such is notably the case when the content of the hallucinations proves to be consistent with the conclusions that result from secondary, tertiary or quaternary arguments. Auditory hallucinations have then the effect of reinforcing the latter conclusions. The instance below constitutes a case where an auditory hallucination comes to reinforce the conclusion of a tertiary delusional argument of telepathy. In that case, the hallucinated content resides in the fact that the patient hears the voice of his friend Joseph saying “I know the slightest of your thoughts”:
(42) ∴ in T50 I thought that people know of my thoughts
(43) in T100 I heard Joseph saying: “I know the slightest of your thoughts”
(44) ∴ this confirms that people know of my thoughts
In a similar way, the following instance has the effect of reinforcing the conclusion which results from a quaternary delusional argument, where the hallucinated content consist of a voice heard by the patient that says: “You come from the planet Mars”:
(19) ∴ in T50 I thought I was an extraterrestrial
(45) in T100 I heard a voice saying : “You come from the planet Mars”
In a general way, we see here how hallucinations constitute an element which has the effect of reinforcing considerably the conclusions resulting from delusional arguments. The hallucinations have then the effect of reinforcing the strength and the consistency of the beliefs’ system of the patient, thus contributing to its maintenance, and rendering then his/her ideas more resistant to contrary argumentation.
6. Comparison with other cognitive models of delusions
The present model, as we can see it, mainly emphasises a cognitive approach of delusions encountered in schizophrenia. This model introduces a fundamental cognitive element, but also leaves room to a neurophysiological element (at the origin of apophenia), the role of which proves to be essential. One can notice finally that the model which has just been described turns out to be compatible with some other accounts of delusional ideas met in schizophrenia.
The present analysis, to begin with, is susceptible of inserting itself as part of the adaptation of Albert Ellis’ ABC-analysis described by Chadwick et al. (1996). In this context, the internal and external events with regard to the patient, that are the premises of primary delusional arguments, constitute the As. The primary, secondary, tertiary and quaternary delusional arguments, can also be assimilated to the Bs. Lastly, the negative emotions (anger, anxiety, frustration, etc.) felt by the patient, that result there from the conclusions of delusional tertiary and quaternary arguments, constitute the Cs. As we can see it, the present analysis leads, in comparison with the standard ABC-analysis, to distinguish several steps at the level of the Bs. This distinction is important, since it allows to distinguish several steps whose function is different, within the reasoning that leads to delusional ideas. Thus, the B1s (primary delusional arguments) are instances that lead to the attribution of a causality relationship between internal and external (to the patient) phenomena; the B2s (secondary delusional arguments) result from a generalisation of inductive nature; the B3s (tertiary delusional arguments) correspond to an interpretative step at a monothematic level; finally, the B4s (quaternary delusional arguments) are characteristic of a step of interpretation at a polythematic level, the conclusion of which truly constitutes a global explicative theory of the abnormal phenomena undergone by the patient. On the other hand, we are led there to distinguish between those parts of the patient’s reasoning which are globally valid (the B2s, B3s and B4s) and the part which is invalid (the B1s, based on post hoc fallacy). Such nuanced point of view should be likely to preserve – what constitutes one of the key points of cognitive and behaviour therapy – the therapeutic alliance, i.e., the relation of collaboration between the patient and the therapist aiming at shared objectives in the struggle against the illness. As we can see it, the present analysis leads to especially emphasise post hoc fallacy, which constitutes the weakness in the patient’s reasoning, but the repeated instances of which, triggered by apophenia, truly constitute the building block of the delusional construction.
The present model also has number of affinity with the approaches which are at the root of cognitive therapy of schizophrenia (Kingdon & Turkington 1994; Kingdon & Turkington 2005; Chadwick & al. 1996; Beck & Rector 2000). In this type of approach, the therapist sets out to reduce progressively the patient’s degree of belief in his/her delusional polythematic ideas. To this end, the therapist suggests the patient, in a spirit of dialogue of Socratic inspiration, to elaborate alternative hypotheses; he also teaches the patient the approach which consists in searching elements likely to confirm or to disconfirm his/her own hypotheses, as well as to build out alternative hypotheses. The contribution of the present analysis with regard to cognitive therapy of schizophrenia is likely to manifest itself in several ways. It proves to be useful to specify then, for the clinician, what could be such contribution, and to also provide a specific framework in which the present model will possibly be tested. The distinction of different steps in the development of delusions allows first to distinguish between different hypotheses corresponding to the conclusions of primary, secondary, ternary and quaternary arguments. The degree of belief associated with each of these levels of hypotheses is also susceptible of being evaluated separately, by notably allowing to determinate then at which level resides the strongest degree of conviction. In the same way, each of the conclusions of the primary, secondary, tertiary or quaternary arguments, will possibly be tested (confirmed/infirmed) and give room for the elaboration of alternative hypotheses (David Kingdon, personal communication). For example, at the level of primary delusional arguments, it will be possible to consider the belief according to which the presenter said in T2: “You should not drink!” because the patient was drinking an aperitif in T1; this hypothesis will possibly give rise to a search for evidence, and then confronted with an alternative hypothesis such as: the presenter said in T2: “You should not drink!” because it was scheduled in the script of the television program. At the level of tertiary delusional arguments, the hypothesis according to which television speaks about the patient will also possibly be the object of a search for evidence, etc.
The interest for the clinician of the present approach resides, second, in the fact that it provides the patient with an alternative global explanation of the abnormal phenomena that he/she undergoes. The delusional construction of the patient constitutes, as we did see it, a theory which allows him/her to explain all the abnormal phenomena that he/she experiences. On can assume in this respect, that the fact for the patient to get a satisfactory theory explaining all abnormal phenomena which he/she experiences, is also likely to play an important role in the maintenance of his/her delusional system. In this context, the present analysis allows to propose to the patient an alternative explicative theory, grounded on apophenia and the different steps of reasoning which result from it. Such theory distinguishes itself from the explicative theory with which the patient is usually confronted (according to the common elliptical point of view, the latter is “mad”) and proves to be less stigmatising, since the reasoning which leads to delusions is notably considered here as normal. For this reason, one can assume that the patient could be more willing to adhere to the present alternative theory, as a global explanation of the abnormal phenomena which he/she experiences.
As we did see it, the present model conforms mainly with the one developed by Brendan Maher (1974; 1988; 1999), based on the fact that delusions result from a broadly normal interpretation of the abnormal phenomena undergone by the patient. The present analysis also specifies with regard to Maher’s model that apophenia (eventually associated with hallucinations) constitutes an abnormal perception which is enough for giving rise to delusional polythematic ideas met in schizophrenia. It has then been objected, as we did see it, to Maher’s model, that it did not allow to account for the fact that delusions can also take place in seemingly normal conditions, especially in a patient not suffering from hallucinations. But the present model points out that such conditions are not normal, since apophenia is present in such a patient. Since apophenia leads to abnormal perceptions, the essential factor described by Maher at the origin of delusional ideas, is therefore present as well. On the second hand, the present model also provides some elements of response with regard to the second objection, formulated against Maher’s model, by Davies and Coltheart (2000), according to which it does not allow to describe how delusional beliefs are adopted and maintained in spite of their implausible nature. The present model, however, sets out first to describe step-by-step the type of reasoning which leads to the adoption of polythematic delusions. By its structure, this type of reasoning appears mainly normal. It proceeds by enumeration of some instances, and then by generalisation and lastly, by interpretation. The present model also provides, as far as I can see, an answer to the criticism raised by Davies and Coltheart with regard to Maher’s model, who blame the latter for not describing how delusional beliefs are maintained in the patient’s belief system, in spite of their implausible nature. In the present model, as we did see it, it is the fact that new instances are generated every day which explains that beliefs are maintained. For when delusional beliefs are established in the patient’s belief system at the end of the stage of their formation, they are then maintained because apophenia continues to trigger every dayiii new instances of primary delusional argument. The latter come, in the patient’s mind, to confirm the conclusions of delusional arguments at a secondary, tertiary and quaternary level, already established at the stage of the formation of delusional ideas. From this point of view, there is no essential difference in the present model in the way that the formation and the maintenance delusional ideas take place. For as we did see it, the building block of the delusional construction is constituted there by the instances of primary delusional arguments, triggered by apophenia. And these instances which concur to the formation of delusional ideas, also ensure their maintenance every day, by confirming the conclusions of secondary, tertiary and quaternary arguments, which are already established at the stage of the formation of delusional ideasiv.
Finally, the model which has just been described provides, as far as I can see, in comparison with Maher’s model, an element which proves to be necessary in the context of an explicative model of polythematic delusions. This element consists of an answer to the question of why the content of delusional ideas in schizophrenia identifies itself most often with delusions of reference, of telepathy, of thought insertion, of influence and of control. As it was exposed above, the answer provided by the present model is that a mechanism of the same nature, grounded on post hoc fallacy, leads to the development of these different delusional topics. In primary delusional arguments of reference, of telepathy or of influence, an event which is internal to the patient precedes an external event. And in the case of a primary delusional argument of control, this structure is simply reversed: it is an external event which precedes an event of the patient’s internal life.
We see it finally, the preceding analysis allows to justify and to reinforce Maher’s initial model. In this context, one can notice that one of the consequences of the present model is that the sole apophenia, associated with normal reasoning, turns out to be sufficient to give rise to the emergence and the maintenance of a delusional systemv.
References
Bayne, Tim & Pacherie, Elisabeth, “In Defense of the Doxastic Conception of Delusions”, Mind and Language, vol. 20-2, 2005, p. 163-88.
Bayne, Tim & Pacherie, Elisabeth, “Experience, Belief, and the Interpretive Fold”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, vol. 11-1, 2004, p. 81-86
Beck, Aaron & Rector, Neil, “Cognitive Therapy of Schizophrenia: A New Therapy for the New Millenium”, American Journal of Psychotherapy, vol. 54-3, 2000, p. 291-300.
Beck, Aaron, “Delusions: A Cognitive perspective”, Journal of Cognitive Psychotherapy, vol. 16-4, 2002, p. 455-468.
Bentall, Richard & Kaney, Sue, “Content specific information processing in persecutory delusions: an investigation using the emotional stroop test”, British Journal of medical Psychology, vol. 62, 1989, p. 355-364.
Bentall, Richard, Kinderman, P., & Kaney, S., “Self, attributional processes and abnormal beliefs: Towards a model of persecutory delusions”, Behaviour Research and Therapy, vol. 32, 1994, p. 331-341.
Bortolotti, Lisa, “Delusions and the background of rationality”, Mind and Language, 20-2, 2005, p.189-208.
Bressan, Paola, “The Connection Between Random Sequences, Everyday Coincidences, and Belief in the Paranormal”, Applied Cognitive Psychology, vol. 16, 2002, p. 17-34.
Brugger, Peter, “From Haunted Brain to Haunted Science: A Cognitive Neuroscience View of Paranormal and Pseudoscientific Thought”, in Hauntings and Poltergeists: Multidisciplinary Perspectives, Houran, J., & Lange, R. (Eds), North Carolina: McFarland, 2001.
Brundage, B.E., “What I wanted to know but was afraid to ask”, Schizophrenia Bulletin, vol. 9, 1983, p. 583-585.
Campbell, John, “Rationality, Meaning, and the Analysis of Delusion”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, vol. 8-2/3, 2001, p. 89-100.
Chadwick, Paul, Birchwood, M., & Trower, P., Cognitive Therapy for Delusions, Voices, and Paranoia, Chichester: Wiley, 1996.
Chapman, L.J., Chapman, J.P., The genesis of delusions, in T.F. Oltmanns, B.A. Maher (Eds), Delusional beliefs, New York: Wiley, 1988, p. 167-183.
Clarke, Isabel, « Madness and Mysticism: clarifying the mystery », Network: The Scientific and Medical Network Review, vol. 72, 2000, p. 11-14.
Conrad, K., Die beginnende Schizophrenie. Versuch einer Gestaltanalyse des Wahns, Stuttgart: Thieme, 1958.
Davies, M. & Coltheart, M., Langdon, R. & Breen, N., “Monothematic delusions: Towards a two-factor account”, Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, vol. 8-2, 2001, p. 133–158.
Davies, Martin & Coltheart, Max, “Introduction: Pathologies of Belief”, Mind and Language, vol. 15, 2000, p.1-46.
Ellis, Albert, Reason and emotion in psychotherapy, New York: Lyle Stuart, 1962.
Engel, Pascal, “Peut-on parler de croyances délirantes ?”, in J. Chemouni, dir. Clinique de l’intentionnalité, In-Press, Paris, 2001, p. 157-173.
Fear, Christopher & Healy David, “Probabilistic reasoning in obsessive-compulsive and delusional disorders”, Psychological Medicine, vol. 27, 1997, p. 199-208.
Fowler, David, Garety, P. & Kuipers, E., Cognitive behaviour therapy for psychosis: theory and practice, Chichester: Wiley, 1995.
Garety, Philippa, Hemsley, D. & Wessely, S., “Reasoning in deluded schizophrenic and paranoid patients”, Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, vol. 179, 1991, p. 194-201.
Garety, Philippa & Hemsley, David, Delusions: Investigations into the Psychology of Delusional Reasoning, Maudsley Monograph, Psychology Press, 1994.
Garety, Philippa, Kuipers, E., Fowler, D., Freeman, D. & Bebbington, P., “A cognitive model of the positive symptoms of psychosis”, Psychological Medicine, vol. 31, 2001, p. 189-195.
Hemsley, David, “Disorders of perception and cognition in schizophrenia”, Revue européenne de Psychologie Appliquée, vol. 42-2, 1992, p. 105-114. Jonas E., Schulz-Hardt S., Frey D., & Thelen N. “Confirmation bias in sequential information search after preliminary decisions: an expansion of dissonance theoretical research on selective exposure to information”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, vol. 80, 2001, p. 557-571.
Kaney, Sue & Bentall, Richard, “Persecutory delusions and attributional style”, British Journal of Medical Psychology, vol. 62, 1989, p. 191-198.
Kaney, Sue, Wolfenden, M., Dewey, M.E. & Bentall, R.P, “Persecutory delusions and recall of threatening and non-threatening propositions”, British Journal of Clinical Psychology, vol. 31, 1991, p. 85-87.
Kingdon, David, & Turkington, Douglas, Cognitive-behavioural Therapy of Schizophrenia, New York: Guilford, 1994.
Kingdon, David, & Turkington, Douglas, Cognitive Therapy of Schizophrenia, New York, London: Guilford, 2005.
Maher, Brendan, “Delusional thinking and perceptual disorder”, Journal of Individual Psychology, vol. 30, 1974, p. 98-113.
Maher, Brendan, “Anomalous experiences and delusional thinking: the logic of explanations“, in Delusional Beliefs, Oltmanns, T. F., & Maher, B. A. (Eds), New York: Wiley, 1988, p. 15-33.
Maher, Brendan, “Anomalous experience in everyday life: Its significance for psychopathology”, The Monist, vol. 82, 1999, p. 547-570.
Martin, Bruce, “Coincidences: Remarkable or random”. Skeptical Inquirer, vol. 22-5, 1998, p. 23-27. Nickerson, Raymond, “Confirmation Bias: A Ubiquitous Phenomenon in Many Guises”, Review of General Psychology, vol. 2, 1998, p. 175-220.
Pacherie E, Green M, Bayne T. “Phenomenology and delusions: who put the ‘alien’ in alien control?”, Consciousness and Cognition, vol. 15, 2006, p. 566–577.
Sass, Louis, The paradoxes of delusion: Wittgenstein, Schreber and the schizophrenic mind, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1994.
Schneider, Carl, Die Psychologie der Schizophrenen, Leipzig: Thieme, 1930.
Spitzer, Manfred, “A neurocomputational approach to delusions”, Comprehensive Psychiatry, vol. 36, 1995, p. 83-105.
Stanton, Biba & David, Anthony, “First-person accounts of delusions”, Psychiatric Bulletin, vol. 24, 2000, p. 333-336.
Stephens, Lynn & George Graham, “Reconcevoir le délire”, Philosophiques, vol. 33-1, 2006, p. 183-196.
Stone, Tony & Young, Andrew, “Delusions and brain injury: the philosophy and psychology of belief”, Mind and Language, vol. 12, 1997, p. 327-364.
Young, Andrew , “Delusions”, The Monist, vol. 82, 1999, p. 571-589.
i Monothematic delusions are not included into the scope of the present study.
ii One can notice that a neurophysiological explanation on the origin of apophenia is provided by Manfred Spitzer (1995, p. 100). He describes then how the latter is linked to the level of activity of dopamine and of norepinephrine, which have an influence on the value of the signal/noise ratio that is at the root of the activation of neural circuits: “if the signal to noise ratio is too high, (…) small environmental signals (i.e. perceptions to which we would normally pay little or no attention at all) may become amplified to a degree that is much higher than usual. This could result in experiences of “significant events” when merely ordinary events were in fact happening”. Spitzer shows then how apophenia can be the consequence of an imbalance at the dopamine level. By placing normally insignificant events (among which the patient’s thoughts) in the foreground, the modification of the signal/noise ratio allows then the particular feeling of interconnection that constitutes apophenia to occur. Under these conditions, one can notably conceive of how the patient’s thoughts can appear to him/her as prominent so as to be put on the same plan, then put in relationship with external facts such as the words pronounced by a TV presenter.
iii As an anonymous referee for Philosophiques suggests, it would be necessary to quantify precisely the frequency of these instances. This could be made in a separate study.
iv These elements of response with regard to the way the maintenance of polythematic delusions takes place need to be supplemented, especially as regards the way the conclusions of quaternary delusional arguments are put in coherence with the rest of the patient’s beliefs, takes place. Such analysis, which requires subsequent work, is however beyond the scope of the present study.
v I am very grateful to David Kingdon, Albert Ellis, Eugen Fischer, Robert Chapman and two anonymous referees for Philosophiques for very helpful comments on ancestor versions and earlier drafts.
In a previous article (Complements to a theory of cognitive distorsions, Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 2007), we introduced some elements aimed at contributing to a general theory of cognitive distortions. Based on the reference class, the duality and the system of taxa, these elements allow to define the general cognitive distortions as well as the specific cognitive distortions. This model is extended here to the description of two other classical cognitive distortions: over-generalisation and mislabelling. The definition of the two latter cognitive distortions is based on prior differentiation between three levels of reasoning: primary, secondary and ternary pathogenic arguments. The latter analysis also leads to define two other cognitive distortions which insert themselves into this framework: ill-grounded inductive projection and confirmation bias.
This article is cited in:
Richard-Lepouriel H., Bipolar disorder, self-stigma and cognitive restructuring: A first attempt to support, Journal de Therapie Comportementale et Cognitive, Volume 27, 2017
Juliette Marty, Et si vous étiez trop perfectionniste ? Eyrolles, 2021
Theory of Cognitive Distortions: Over-generalisation and Labeling
In Franceschi (2007), we set out to introduce several elements aimed at contributing to a general theory of cognitive distortions. These elements are based on three fundamental notions: the reference class, the duality and the system of taxa. With these three elements, we could define within the same conceptual framework the following general cognitive distortions: dichotomous reasoning, disqualification of one pole, minimisation and maximisation, requalification in the other pole and omission of the neutral. We could also describe as specific cognitive distortions: disqualification of the positive, selective abstraction and catastrophism. In the present article, we offer to define and to situate, within the same conceptual framework, two other classical cognitive distortions: over-generalisation and mislabelling.
Over-generalisation and mislabelling constitute two of the twelve traditionally defined cognitive distortions: emotional reasoning; over-generalisation; arbitrary inference; dichotomous reasoning; should statements; divination or mental reading; selective abstraction; disqualification of the positive; maximisation/minimisation; catastrophising; personalisation; mislabelling (Beck 1964, Ellis 1962). Over-generalisation is classically defined as a rough and ill-grounded generalisation, usually including either of the quantifiers “all”, “none”, “never”, “always”. Moreover, it is often described as a cognitive distortion including four subcategories: dichotomous reasoning, selective abstraction, maximisation/minimisation, and disqualification of the positive. Mislabelling is also classically defined as an extreme form of over-generalisation, consisting in the apposition of a label with a strong negative and emotional connotation to oneself or to an external subject.
1. Primary, secondary and ternary pathogenic arguments
Before setting out to define over-generalisation and mislabelling in the present context, it is worth describing preliminarily a structure of pathogenic reasoning (in the etymological sense: engendering suffering), with a general scope, susceptible of being found in some disorders of a very different nature, such as depression, generalised anxiety disorder, body dismorphic disorder, scrupulosity or intermittent explosive disorder. Such structure of reasoning includes several levels of arguments: primary, secondary and ternary. In a simplified way, primary pathogenic arguments are constituted by an enumeration of instances. Secondary pathogenic arguments consist of a generalisation from the latter instances. Lastly, pathogenic ternary arguments are constituted by an interpretation of the latter generalisation. Such reasoning as a whole presents an inductive structure.
At this stage, it is worth mentioning several instances of this type of reasoning. A first instance, susceptible to be found in depression (Beck 1967, 1987), is the following (the symbol denotes the conclusion):
(11)
I gave my ankle a wrench last January
premise1
(12)
I lost my job last February
premise2
(13)
Fifteen days ago, I had an influenza with fever
premise3
(14)
I got into an argument with Lucy last month
premise4
(…)
(…)
(110)
Today, my horoscope is not good
premise10
(2)
∴ Everything that occurs to me is bad
from (11)-(110)
(3)
∴ I am a complete failure!
from (2)
The patient enumerates first some events of his/her past and present life (11)-(110), that he/she qualifies as negative, through a primary stage which consists of an enumeration of instances. Then he/she performs a generalisation (2) from the previous enumeration, which presents the following structure:
(2)
∴ All events that occur to me are negative
from (11)-(110)
Lastly, the patient interprets (3) the latter conclusion by concluding “I am a complete failure!”. Such instance applies then to the reference class of the present and past events of the patient’s life and to the Positive/Negative duality.
One can also mention a reasoning that presents an identical structure, which is susceptible to be met in body dysmorphic disorder (Veale 2004, Rabinowitz & al. 2007). The patient enumerates then different parts of his/her body, which he/she qualifies as ugly. He/she generalises then by concluding that all parts of his/her body are ugly. Finally, he/she adds: “I am ugly!”. The corresponding reasoning applies then to the Beautiful/Ugly duality and to the reference class of the parts of the patient’s body.
In the same way, in a reasoning of identical structure, susceptible to be met in scrupulosity (Teak & Ulug 2001, Miller & Edges 2007), the patient enumerates several instances corresponding to some acts which he/she made previously or recently, and which he/she considers as morally bad. He/she concludes then: “Everything I do is bad, morally reprehensible”, and he/she further interprets it by concluding: “I am a horrible sinner!”. Such conclusion is likely to trigger an intense feel of guilt and a compulsive practice of religious rituals. The corresponding instance applies here to the duality Good/Evil and to the reference class of the present and past actions of the patient’s life.
Lastly, an instance of this structure of reasoning can contribute to the development of hostility, of a potentially aggressive attitude toward other people. In that case, the patient concludes regarding an external subject: “All acts that he committed toward me are bad”. He/she concludes then: “He is a bastard!”. Such conclusion can then play a role in intermittent explosive disorder (Coccaro & al. 1998, Galovski & al. 2002). In such case, the over-generalisation applies to the Good/Evil duality and to the reference class of the actions of an external subject with regard to the patient.
At this step, it is worth describing in more detail each of the three stages – primary, secondary and ternary – which compose this type of reasoning.
Primary pathogenic arguments
The first step in the aforementioned type of reasoning, consists for the patient to enumerate some instances. The general structure of each instance is as follows:
(1i)
The object xi of the class of reference E has property Ā (in the duality A/Ā)
premisei
In the aforementioned example applied to depression, the patient enumerates some events of his/her present and past life, which he/she qualifies as negative, under the form:
(1i)
The event Ei of negative nature occurred to me
premisei
Different instances corresponding to this cognitive process can be described under the form of a primary pathogenic argument, the structure of which is the following:
(1a)
The event E1 occurred to me
premise
(1b)
The event E1 was of a negative nature
premise
(1)
∴ The event E1 of a negative nature occurred to me
from (1a), (1b)
By such cognitive process, the patient is led to the conclusion according to which some negative event did occur to him/her.
From a deductive point of view, this type of argument proves to be completely valid (the conclusion is true if the premises are true) since the very event presents well, objectively, a negative nature. However, this type of primary argument can turn out to be fallacious, when the very event presents, objectively, a positive or neutral nature. The flaw in the reasoning resides then in the fact that the premise (1b) turns then out to be false. Such can be case for example if the patient makes use of a specific cognitive distortion such as requalification in the negative. In such case, the patient considers as negative an event the nature of which is objectively positive.
Secondary pathogenic arguments
At the level of the above-mentioned reasoning, secondary pathogenic arguments are constituted by the sequence which proceeds by generalisation, from the instances (11) to (110), according to the following structure:
(2)
∴ All elements xi of the class of reference E have property Ā
from (11)-(110)
Such over-generalisation leads then to the conclusion “All events that occur to me are bad” (depression); “All parts of my body are ugly” (body dysmorphic disorder); “All my acts are morally reprehensible” (scrupulosity); “All acts that he committed toward me are bad” (intermittent explosive disorder).
From a deductive point of view, such generalisation may constitute a completely valid argument. Indeed, the resulting generalisation constitutes a correct deductive reasoning, if the premises (11)-(110) are true. However, it often proves to be that the premises of the argument are false. Such is notably the case when the patient counts among the elements having property Ā, some elements which objectively have the opposite property A. The flaw in the argument resides then in a requalification in the other pole related to some elements and the enumeration of instances includes then some false premises, thus invalidating the resulting generalisation. In such case, secondary pathogenic argument turns out to be ungrounded, because of the falseness of some premises.
In other cases, the secondary pathogenic argument turns out to be fallacious from an inductive standpoint. For some positive (or neutral) events can well have been omitted in the corresponding enumeration of instances. Such omission can result from the use of general cognitive distortions, such as the omission of the neutral or disqualification of the positive. In such case, the elements of the relevant class of reference are only partly taken into account, thus biasing the resulting generalisation. The corresponding reasoning remains then logically valid and sound, but fundamentally incorrect of an inductive point of view, because it does only take partly into account the relevant instances within the reference class. Such feature of over-generalisation – a conclusion resulting from a valid reasoning from a deductive point of view, but inductively wrong – allows to explain how it notably succeeds in deceiving patients whose level of intelligence can otherwise prove to be high.
Ternary pathogenic arguments
It is worth mentioning, lastly, the role played by pathogenic ternary arguments which consist, at the level of the aforementioned reasoning, of the following sequence:
(2)
All events that occur to me are of a negative nature
premise
(3)
∴ I am a complete failure!
from (2)
In such argument, the premise is constituted by the conclusion (2) of the secondary pathogenic argument, of which, in an additional stage (3), the patient aims at making sense by interpreting it. It consists here of a case of mislabelling. At the stage of a ternary pathogenic argument, mislabelling can thus take the following forms: “I am a complete failure!” (depression); “I am ugly!” (bodily dysmorphic disorder); “I am a horrible sinner!” (scrupulosity); “He is a bastard! “ (intermittent explosive disorder). In the present context, mislabelling proves to be an invalid argument, which constitutes a rough and unjustified interpretation of the over-generalisation (2).
2. Over-generalisation
At this stage, we are in a position to give a definition of over-generalisation, by drawing a distinction between general and specific over-generalisations. A general over-generalisation applies to any duality and to any reference class. It can be analysed as the ill-grounded conclusion of a secondary pathogenic argument, the premises of which include some general cognitive distortions: dichotomous reasoning, disqualification of one pole, arbitrary focus, minimisation/maximisation, omission of the neutral or requalification in the other pole. It consists of an ungrounded inductive reasoning, because the resulting generalisation is based on an incorrect counting of the corresponding instances. In the same way, a specific over-generalisation consists of an instance of a general over-generalisation, applied to a given duality and reference class. Thus, the specific over-generalisation “All events which occur to me are of a negative nature” (depression, generalised anxiety disorder) applies to the Positive/Negative duality and to the class of the events of the patient’s life. In the same way, “All parts of my body are ugly” (body dysmorphic disorder) is a specific over-generalisation that applies to the reference class of the parts of the patient’s body and to the Beautiful/Ugly duality.
3. Ungrounded inductive projection
At this step, it proves to be useful to describe another error of reasoning, which is likely to manifest itself at the stage of secondary pathogenic arguments. It consists of an ill-grounded inductive projection. The latter concludes, from the preceding over-generalisation (2), that a new instance will occur in the near future. Such instance is susceptible to be met in depression (Miranda & al. 2008), as well as in generalised anxiety disorder (Franceschi 2008). In the context of depression, such inductive projection presents the following form:
(2)
All events that occur to me are of a negative nature
premise
(111a)
The future event E11 of a negative nature may occur
premise
(111b)
∴ The future event E11 of a negative nature will occur
from (2), (111a)
The corresponding conclusion is susceptible of contributing to depression, notably by triggering the patient’s feeling of despair. Other instances of this type of conclusion are: “My next action will be morally reprehensible” (scrupulosity), or “The next act that he will commit toward me will be bad” (intermittent explosive disorder).
4. Confirmation bias
The cognitive process which has just been described illustrates how over-generalisation contributes to the formation of pathogenic ideas. However, a process of the same nature is also likely to concur to their maintenance. For once the over-generalisation (2) has been established by means of the above reasoning, its maintenance is made as soon as an instance occurs that confirms the generalisation according to which all elements xi of the reference class E have property Ā. This constitutes a confirmation bias, for the patient does only count those elements which present the property Ā, without taking into account those which have the opposite property A, thus disconfirming generalisation (2). Hence, in depression or generalised anxiety disorder, when a new negative event occurs, the patient concludes from it that it confirms that all events which occur to him/her are of a negative nature.
We see it finally, the above developments suggest a classification of cognitive distortions, depending on whether they manifest themselves at the level of primary, secondary or ternary pathogenic arguments. Thus, among the cognitive distortions which arise at the stage of primary pathogenic arguments, one can distinguish: on the one hand, the general cognitive distortions (dichotomous reasoning, disqualification of one pole, minimisation/maximisation, requalification into the other pole, omission of the neutral) and on the other hand, the specific cognitive distortions (disqualification of the positive, requalification into the negative, selective abstraction, catastrophising). Morevoer, among the cognitive distortions which manifest themselves at the stage of secondary pathogenic arguments, one can mention over-generalisation (at the stage of the formation of pathogenic ideas), ill-grounded inductive projection, and confirmation bias (at the stage of the maintenance of pathogenic ideas). Mislabelling, finally, is susceptible to occur at the level of ternary pathogenic arguments.
References
Beck A. Thinking and depression: Theory and therapy. Archives of General Psychiatry, 1964, 10, 561-571.
Beck, A. Depression: Clinical, experimental, and theoretical aspects, Harper & Row, New York, 1967.
Beck, A. Cognitive models of depression. Journal of Cognitive Psychotherapy, 1, 1987, 5-37.
Coccaro E., Richard J., Kavoussi R., Mitchell E., Berman J., Lish J. Intermittent explosive disorder-revised: Development, reliability, and validity of research criteria. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 39-6, 1998, 368-376.
Eckhardt C., Norlander B., Deffenbacher J., The assessment of anger and hostility: a critical review, Aggression and Violent Behavior, 9-1, 2004, 17-43.
Ellis A. Reason and Emotion in Psychotherapy, Lyle Stuart, New York, 1962.
Franceschi P. Compléments pour une théorie des distorsions cognitives. Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 2007, 17-2, 84-88. English translation.
Franceschi P. Théorie des distorsions cognitives : application à l’anxiété généralisée. Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 2008, 18, 127-131. English translation.
Galovski T., Blanchard E., Veazey C. Intermittent explosive disorder and other psychiatric co-morbidity among court-referred and self-referred aggressive drivers. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 40-6, 2002, 641-651.
Miller C., Hedges D. Scrupulosity disorder: An overview and introductory analysis. Journal of Anxiety Disorders, 2007, 22-6, 1042-1048.
Miranda R., Fontes M., Marroquín B. Cognitive content-specificity in future expectancies: Role of hopelessness and intolerance of uncertainty in depression and GAD symptoms. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 46-10, 2008, 1151-1159.
Tek C., Ulug B. Religiosity and religious obsessions in obsessive–compulsive disorder. Psychiatry Research, 2001, 104-2, 99-108.
Rabinowitz D., Neziroglu F., Roberts M. Clinical application of a behavioral model for the treatment of body dysmorphic disorder. Cognitive and Behavioral Practice, 2007, 14-2, 231-237.
Veale D. Advances in a cognitive behavioural model of body dysmorphic disorder. Body Image, 2004, 1, 113-125.
English translation of a paper published in French in the Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 2010, 20-2, pages 51-55 under the title “Théorie des distorsions cognitives : la personnalisation”.
In a previous paper (Complements to a theory of cognitive distorsions, Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 2007), we did present some elements aimed at contributing to a general theory of cognitive distortions. Based on the reference class, the duality and the system of taxa, these elements led to distinguish between the general cognitive distortions (dichotomous reasoning, disqualification of one pole, minimisation, maximisation) and the specific cognitive distortions (disqualifying the positive, selective abstraction, catastrophism). By also distinguishing between three levels of reasoning – the instantiation stage, the interpretation stage and the generalisation stage – we did also define two other cognitive distortions: over-generalisation and mislabelling (Théorie des distorsions cognitives : la sur-généralisation et l’étiquetage, Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 2009). We currently extend this model to another classical cognitive distortion: personalisation.
This article is cited in:
Juliette Marty, Et si vous étiez trop perfectionniste ? Eyrolles, 2021
Theory of Cognitive Distortions: Personalisation
In Franceschi (2007), we set out to introduce several elements intended to contribute to a general theory of cognitive distortions. These elements are based on three fundamental notions: the reference class, the duality and the system of taxa. With the aid of these three elements, we could define within the same conceptual framework the general cognitive distortions such as dichotomous reasoning, disqualification of one pole, minimisation and maximisation, as well as requalification in the other pole and omission of the neutral. In the same way, we could describe as specific cognitive distortions: disqualification of the positive, selective abstraction and catastrophising. In Franceschi (2009), we introduced three levels of reasoning – the instantiation stage, the interpretation stage and the generalisation stage, which allowed to define within the same conceptual framework, two other classical cognitive distortions: over-generalisation and mislabelling. In the present paper, we set out to define and to situate in this conceptual framework another classical cognitive distortion: personalisation.
Personalisation constitutes one of but twelve classically defined cognitive distortions: emotional reasoning; over-generalisation; arbitrary inference; dichotomous reasoning; should statements; divination or mind-reading; selective abstraction; disqualification of the positive; maximisation/minimisation; catastrophising; personalisation; mislabelling (Ellis 1962, Beck 1964). Personalisation is usually defined as the fact of attributing unduly to oneself the cause of an external event. For example, seeing a person who laughs, the patient thinks that it is because of his/her physical appearance. Also, the patient makes himself/herself responsible for a negative event, in an unjustified way. If his/her companion then failed his/her examination, the patient estimates that is due to the fact that he/she is depressed. In what follows, we propose first to clarify the definition of personalisation and to situate it in the context of the theory of cognitive distortions (Franceschi 2007, 2009). Secondly, we set out to clarify the relationships existing between personalisation and several close notions mentioned in the literature: personalising bias (Langdon et al. 2006), ideas of reference (Startup & Startup 2005, Meyer & Lenzenweger 2009) and delusions of reference.
Personalisation and post hoc fallacy
We will set out first to highlight the mere structures of the cases of personalisation. Let us consider the aforementioned example where the patient sees a person who laughs and thinks that this one laughs because of the patient’s physical appearance. This constitutes an instance of personalisation. We can describe more accurately the reasoning which underlies such instance (in what follows, the symbol denotes the conclusion):
(P11)
in T1 I went for a walk
premiss1
(P12)
in T2 the peasant started to laugh
premiss2
(P13)
∴ in T2 the peasant started to laugh because he saw that in T1 I went for a walk
conclusion1
(P14)
∴ in T2 the peasant made fun of me
conclusion2
The patient puts here in relationship an internal event (“I went for a walk”) with an external event (“the peasant started to laugh”). He/she concludes then that the internal event is the cause of the external event. In this stage, the patient “personalises” an external event, which he/she considers to be the effect of an internal event, while this external event is in reality devoid of any relationship with the patient himself/herself. In a subsequent stage (P14), the patient interprets the previous conclusion (P13) by considering that the peasant made fun of him.
At this stage, it is worth wondering about the specific nature of the patient’s error of reasoning. It appears here that both premises (P11) and (P12) constitute genuine facts and therefore turn out to be true. On the other hand, the conclusion (P13) which concludes to the existence of a relation of causality between two consecutive events E1 (“In T1 I went for a walk”) and E2 (“In T2 the peasant started to laugh”) appears to be unjustified. Indeed, both premises are only establishing a relation of anteriority between the two consecutive facts E1 and E2. And the conclusion (P13) which deducts from it a relation of causality turns out therefore to be too strong. The argument proves here to be invalid and the corresponding reasoning is then fallacious. The corresponding error of reasoning, which concludes to a relation of causality whereas there is only a mere relation of anteriority, is classically termed post hoc fallacy, according to the Latin sentence “Post hoc, ergo propter hoc” (after this therefore because of this). It consists here of a very common error of reasoning, which is notably at the root of many superstitions (Martin 1998, Bressan 2002).
In this context, we can point out that the case of post hoc fallacy which has just been described as an argument of personalisation, also constitutes a case of arbitrary inference, another classically defined cognitive distortion.
Steps of instantiation, of interpretation and of generalisation at the level of the arguments of personalisation
At this step, it proves to be useful to draw a distinction between the levels of arguments that lead to personalisation as cognitive distortion. This leads to differentiate three levels within the arguments of personalisation, among the reasoning’ stages. The latter correspond respectively to three different functions: it consists of the successive stages of instanciation, of interpretation and of generalisation. To this end, it is useful to describe the whole reasoning which underlies the arguments of personalisation and which includes the three aforementioned stages:
(P11)
in T1 I went for a walk
premiss11
(P12)
in T2 the peasant started to laugh
premiss12
(P13)
∴ en T2 the peasant started to laugh because he saw that in T1 I went for a walk
conclusion11
(P14)
∴ in T2 the peasant made fun of me
conclusion12
(P21)
in T3 I was leafing through a magazine in the library
premiss21
(P22)
in T4, the librarian smirked
premiss22
(P23)
∴ en T4 the librarian smirked because in T3 I was leafing through a magazine in the library
conclusion21
(P24)
∴ in T4, the librarian made fun of me
conclusion22
(P31)
in T5 I did enter in the show-room
premiss31
(P32)
in T6, my colleagues started to laugh
premiss32
(P33)
∴ in T6, my colleagues started to laugh because in T5 I did enter in the show-room
conclusion31
(P34)
∴ in T6, my colleagues were laughing at me
conclusion32
(…)
(P105)
∴ people make fun of me
from (P14)-(P104)
Here, the instances of the previous arguments (P11)-(P13), (P21)-(P23), (P31)-(P33), etc. constitute primary stages of arguments of personalisation, by which the patient considers that an event related to him/her is the cause of an external event. This type of argument corresponds to the stage of instantiation. As mentioned earlier, such argument is fallacious since it is based on post hoc fallacy. In a subsequent stage the function of which is interpretative, and that is aimed at making sense of the conclusions (P13), (P23), (P33), … of the instances of arguments of the previous type, the patient interprets it by concluding that some people made fun of him. Such conclusions (P14), (P24), (P34) appear to be grounded, inasmuch as the premisses (P13), (P23), (P33) are true. Finally, in a subsequent stage of generalisation, the patient enumerates some instances or circumstances where he/she thinks that people laughed or made fun of him/her ((P14), (P24), (P34), …) and generalises then to the conclusion (P105) according to which people make fun of him/her. This last stage is of an inductive nature, and corresponds to an enumerative induction, the structure of which is the following:
(P14)
in T2 the peasant made fun of me
conclusion12
(P24)
in T4, the librarian made fun of me
conclusion22
(P34)
in T6, my colleagues were laughing at me
conclusion32
(…)
(P105)
∴ people make fun of me
from (P14)-(P104)
Given what precedes, we can from now on provide a definition of personalisation. The preceding analysis leads then to distinguish between three stages in arguments of personalisation. At the level of primary arguments of personalisation (stage of instantiation), it consists of the tendency in the patient to establish an unjustified relation of causality between two events, among which one is external and the other one is internal to the patient. The patient personalises then, that is to say puts in relationship with himself/herself, an external event, which proves to be in reality devoid of any relation of causality. The mechanism which underlies such argument consists then of the erroneous attribution of a relation of causality, based on post hoc fallacy. At the level of secondary arguments of personalisation (stage of interpretation), the patient makes sense of the previous conclusion by concluding that at a given time, a person (or several persons) made fun of him, laughed at him, etc. Finally, at the level of arguments of ternary personalisation (stage of generalisation), the patient concludes that, in a general way, people make fun of him.
Personalisation and personalising bias
At this step, it proves to be useful to distinguish personalisation as cognitive distortion from personalising bias. The latter is defined as an attribution bias (“personalising attributional bias”), by whom the patient attributes to other persons rather than to circumstances the cause of a negative event (McKay & al. 2005, Langdon & al. 2006). Personalising bias is often related to polythematic delusions (Kinderman & Bentall 1997, Garety & Freeman 1999, McKay & al. 2005) met in schizophrenia.
Considering this definition, the difference between the two notions can be thus underlined: in personalisation as cognitive distortion, the patient attributes the cause of an external event to an event which concerns the patient himself/herself; on the other hand, in personalising bias the patient attributes the cause of an internal event to external persons. This allows to highlight several fundamental differences between the two notions. Firstly, in personalisation as cognitive distortion, the “person” is the patient himself/herself, while in personalising bias, it consist of external “persons”. Secondly, in the structure of personalisation, an internal event precedes an external event; by contrast, in the scheme of personalising bias, it is an external event which precedes an internal event. Finally, in personalisation as cognitive distortion, the internal event is indifferently of a positive, neutral or negative nature, whereas in personalising bias, the internal event is of a negative type. Hence, it finally proves to be that both notions appear fundamentally distinct.
Personalisation and ideas of reference
It appears also useful, for the sake of clarity, to specify the relationships between personalisation and ideas of reference. It is worth preliminary mentioning that one usually distinguishes between ideas of reference and delusions of reference (Dziegielewski 2002, p. 266). Ideas of reference characterise themselves by the fact that a patient considers that insignificant events relate to himself/herself, while is not the case in reality. For example, the patient hears several persons laugh, and considers, in an unjustified way, that the latter make fun of him/her. In parallel, delusions of reference constitute one of the most salient symptoms noticed in schizophrenia, and leads the patient to be persuaded that the media, television, or the radio speak about him/her or issue messages concerning him/her. Several criteria allow to draw a distinction between ideas of reference and delusions of reference. First, ideas of reference have much less impact on the patient’s life than reference delusions of reference. Second, the degree of conviction which is associated with ideas of reference is far lesser than with delusions of reference. Lastly, ideas of reference (“the neighbour made fun of me”) are related with beliefs the degree of plausibility of which is much stronger than the one which is inherent to delusions of reference (“newspapers speak about me”).
In this context, the aforementioned arguments of personalisation (P11)-(P14), (P21)-(P24), and (P31)-(P34), by whom the patient concludes that some people make fun of him, corresponds completely to the definition of ideas of reference. It appears then that personalisation, such as it was defined above as cognitive distortion, identifies itself with ideas of reference.
Personalisation and delusion of reference
One traditionally distinguishes at the level of polythematic delusions met in schizophrenia between: delusions of reference, delusions of influence, delusions of control, telepathy-like delusions, delusions of grandeur, and delusions of persecution. Delusions of reference leads for example the patient to believe with a very strong conviction that the media, the newspapers, the television speak about him/her.
It is worth describing here a mechanism which is susceptible to lead to the formation of delusions of reference. Such mechanism appears to be grounded on a reasoning (Franceschi 2008) which includes, as well as the above-mentioned primary instances of personalisation, a post hoc fallacy:
(DR11)
in T1 I was drinking an appetizer
premiss11
(DR12)
in T2 the presenter of the show said: “Stop drinking!”
premiss12
(DR13)
∴ in T2 the presenter of the show said: “Stop drinking!” because in T1 I was drinking an appetizer
conclusion11
(DR14)
∴ in T2 the presenter of the show spoke about me
conclusion12
Consider also this second instance :
(DR21)
in T3 I hardly got out of bed
premiss21
(DR22)
in T4 the radio presenter said: “Be forceful:”
premiss22
(DR23)
∴ in T4 the radio presenter said: “Be forceful:” because in T3 I hardly got out of bed
conclusion21
(DR24)
∴ in T4 the radio presenter spoke about me
conclusion22
At the level of the instantial step (DR11)-(DR13), (DR21)-(DR23), … the patient concludes here that an internal event is the cause of an external event. In a further interpretative stage, he/she interprets the conclusions (DR13), (DR23), … of the preceding arguments by considering that the presenters of radio or of television speak about him/her. Finally, in a generalisation step, of inductive nature, the patient enumerates the conclusions (DR14), (DR24), … of secondary arguments (interpretation stage) and generalises thus:
(DR14)
∴ in T2 , the presenter of the show spoke about me
(DR24)
∴ in T4, the radio presenter spoke about me
(…)
(DR105)
∴ the media speak about me
conclusion
It proves then that the structure of the mechanism which leads to the formation of delusions of reference thus described, is identical to that of the reasoning which leads to ideas of reference which is associated with personalisation as cognitive distortion.
Finally, it appears that the preceding developments allow to provide a definition of personalisation and to situate it in the context of cognitive distortions (Franceschi 2007, 2009). Personalisation is then likely to manifest itself at the level of primary, secondary or ternary pathogenic arguments, which correspond respectively to the stages of instantiation, of interpretation, and of generalisation. At the level of primary pathogenic arguments, corresponding to a function of instantiation, it consists of instances, the conclusions of which lead the patient to conclude in an unjustified way that some external events are caused by some of his/her actions. At the level of secondary pathogenic arguments, which correspond to a function of interpretation, personalisation takes the form of a reasoning by which the patient interprets the conclusion of primary pathogenic argument by concluding for example that people make fun of him/her. Finally, at the level of ternary pathogenic arguments, associated with a function of generalisation, the patient generalises from the conclusions of several secondary pathogenic arguments and concludes that, in a general way, people make fun of him/her.
Lastly, it appears that the previous definition of personalisation as cognitive distortion allows to describe precisely the relationships between personalisation and close notions such as personalising bias, ideas of reference and delusions of reference.
References
Beck A. Thinking and depression: Theory and therapy. Archives of General Psychiatry 1964; 10:561-571.
Bressan, P. The Connection Between Random Sequences, Everyday Coincidences, and Belief in the Paranormal. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 2002, 16, 17-34.
Dziegielewski, S. F. DSM-IV-TR in action, Wiley, New York, 2002.
Ellis A. Reason and Emotion in Psychotherapy, Lyle Stuart, New York, 1962.
Franceschi P. Compléments pour une théorie des distorsions cognitives. Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 2007, 17-2, 84-88. English translation: http://cogprints.org/5261/
Franceschi P. Une défense logique du modèle de Maher pour les délires polythématiques. Philosophiques, 2008, 35-2, 451-475. English translation.
Franceschi P. Théorie des distorsions cognitives : la sur-généralisation et l’étiquetage. Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 2009, 19-4. English translation.
Garety, P., Freeman, D., 1999. Cognitive approaches to delusions: a critical review of theories and evidence. British Journal of Clinical Psychology 38, 113-154.
Langdon R., Cornera T., McLarena J., Wardb P. & Coltheart M., 2006, Externalizing and personalizing biases in persecutory delusions: The relationship with poor insight and theory-of-mind, Behaviour Research and Therapy, 44:699-713
Kinderman, P., Bentall, R., 1997. Causal attributions in paranoia and depression: internal, personal, and situational attributions for negative events. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 106 (2), 341- 345.
Martin, B. Coincidences: Remarkable or random. Skeptical Inquirer, 1998, 22-5, 23-27.
McKay, R., Langdon, R. & Coltheart, 2005. M. Paranoia, persecutory delusions and attributional biases, Psychiatry Research, 136, 233–245
Meyer, E., Lenzenweger, M., 2009. The specificity of referential thinking: A comparison of schizotypy and social anxiety, Psychiatry Research, 165, 78-87.
Startup, M., Startup, S., 2005. On two kinds of delusion of reference, Psychiatry Research ,137, 87-92.
English translation and postprint (with additional illustrations) of a paper published in French under the title “Théorie des distorsions cognitives : application à l’anxiété généralisée” in the Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 2008, 18, pp. 127-131. This article follows the contribution to the general theory of cognitive distortions exposed in “Complements to a theory of cognitive distorsions” (Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, 2007). The elements described, namely the reference class, the duality and the system of taxa, are applied here to generalised anxiety disorder. On the one hand, these elements allow to describe the cognitive distortions which are specific to generalised anxiety disorder, consistent with recent work emphasising the role played uncertain situations relative to future events. On the second hand, they allow to define a type of structured reasoning, of inductive nature, which leads to the formation and maintenance of anxious ideas.
This paper is cited in:
Étude des profils de distorsion cognitive en fonction des états anxieux et dépressifs chez des adultes tout-venant, Anita Robert, Nicolas Combalbert, Valérie Pennequin, Annales Médico-psychologiques, revue psychiatrique, Volume 176-3, 2018, pages 225-230
Deperrois Romain & Nicolas Combalbert, Links between cognitive distortions and cognitive emotion regulation strategies in non-clinical young adulthood, in Psychological Applications and Trends, Eb. by C. Pracana & M. Wang, InScience Press, 2019
Nawal Ouhmad, Nicolas Combalbert, Wissam El-Hage, Cognitive distortions and emotion regulation among post traumatic stress disorder victims, in Psychological Applications and Trends, Eb. by C. Pracana & M. Wang, InScience Press, 2019
A.Robert, N.Combalbert, V.Pennequin, R.Deperrois, N.Ouhmad, Création de l’Échelle de Distorsions Cognitives pour adultes (EDC-A) : étude des propriétés psychométriques en population générale et association avec l’anxiété et la dépression, Psychologie Française, 2021
Theory of Cognitive Distortions: Application to Generalised Anxiety Disorder
In Franceschi (2007), we set out to introduce several elements intended to contribute to a general theory of cognitive distortions. These elements are based on three basic notions: the reference class, the duality and the system of taxa. With the help of these three elements, we could define within the same conceptual framework the general cognitive distortions such as dichotomous reasoning, the disqualification of one pole, minimisation and maximisation, as well as the requalification in the other pole and the omission of the neutral. In addition, we could describe as specific cognitive distortions: the disqualification of the positive, selective abstraction and catastrophism.
In what follows, we offer to extend this work by applying it in a specific way to generalised anxiety disorder (GAD), in order to allow their use within cognitive therapy. The present study inserts itself in the context of recent work (Butler & Mathews 1983, 1987, Dalgleish et al. 1997), which notably underlined the major role played, in the context of GAD, by indeterminate situations, and especially by uncertain situations relating to future events. Recent developments, emphasising especially the intolerance with regard to indeterminate future situations, echoed this (Dugas et al. 2004, Canterbury et al. 2004, Carleton et al. 2007).
We shall be interested successively in two main forms of reasoning likely to occur in the context of GAD: on the one hand, the cognitive distortions which are specific to GAD; on the other hand, a structured argument relating to GAD and grounded on inductive logic, which is likely to include one or several of the aforementioned cognitive distortions.
Cognitive distortions in the context of generalized anxiety disorder
The optimal system of taxa
The conceptual framework defined in Franceschi (2007) is based on three fundamental elements: the duality, the reference class, and the system of taxa, which allow to define the general cognitive distortions. These three notions also allow to describe the specific cognitive distortions which are applicable to GAD. In this context, as we will see it, the reference class for the latter specific cognitive distortions identifies itself with the class of future events of the patient’s life. Moreover, the duality assimilates itself to the Positive/Negative duality. Finally, for the sake of the present discussion, we shall make use of the system of taxa (its choice is more or less arbitrary) described in Franceschi (2007), which includes 11 taxa, denoted by E1 to E11, where E6 denotes the neutral taxon. Such conceptual framework allows then to define the specific cognitive distortions in the context of GAD. We offer to examine them in turn.
Dichotomous reasoning
Dichotomous reasoning
An instance of dichotomous reasoning related to GAD consists for the patient to only consider future events from the viewpoint of the extreme taxa corresponding to each pole of the Positive/Negative duality. Hence, the patient only considers future events which present either a very positive, or a very negative nature. All other events, being either neutral, positive or negative to a lesser degree, are thus ignored. This type of reasoning can be analysed as an instance of dichotomous reasoning, applied to the class of the events of the patient’s future life and to the Positive/Negative duality.
Disqualification of one pole
The disqualification of one pole
An instance of the disqualification of one pole related to GAD consists for the patient to only envisage, among future events likely to occur, those which present a negative nature. The patient tends then to be unaware of positive future events that could happen, by considering that they do not count, for this or that reason. In the present context, this type of reasoning can be analysed as an instance of disqualification of one pole, applied to the reference class of the events of the patient’s future life and to the Positive/Negative duality, i.e. disqualification of the positive.
Arbitrary focus on a given modality
Arbitrary focus
In GAD, a typical instance of arbitrary focus, consists for the patient to focus on a possible future event, the nature of which turns out to be negative. This can be analysed as focusing on one of the taxa of the Positive/Negative duality, at the level of the class of the future events of the patient’s life.
Omission of the neutral
Omission of the neutral
A specific instance for GAD consists for the patient to be completely unaware of possible future events the nature of which is neutral, i.e. those which are neither positive nor negative.
Requalification into the other pole
Requalifcation into the other pole
In the context of GAD, the corresponding cognitive distortion consists in requalifying as negative a possible future event, whereas it should be considered objectively as positive. Such cognitive distortion consists of a requalification in the other pole applied to the reference class of the future events of the patient’s life and to the Positive/Negative duality, i.e. requalification in the negative.
Minimisation or maximisation
Maximisation and minimisation
A specific instance of minimisation applied to GAD consists for the patient to consider some possible future events as less positive than they truly are in reality. With maximisation, the patient considers some possible future events as more negative than they objectively are.
Primary, secondary and tertiary anxiogenous arguments
At this stage, it is worth also considering a certain type of reasoning, likely to be met in GAD, which can include several instances of the aforementioned cognitive distortions. This type of reasoning presents an anxiogenous nature, because it leads the patient to predict that a future event of negative nature is going to occur. Such reasoning is underlain by a structure which presents an inductive nature. Before analysing in detail the different steps of the corresponding reasoning, it is worth describing preliminarily its internal structure. The latter is the following (in what follows, the symbol ∴ denotes the conclusion):
(1) the event E1 of negative nature did occur to me
premiss
(2) the event E2 of negative nature did occur to me
premiss
(3) the event E3 of negative nature did occur to me
premiss
(…)
premiss
(10) the event E10 of negative nature did occur to me
premiss
(11) all events that occur to me are of negative nature
from (1)-(10)
(12) « I am always unlucky », « I am ill-fated »
from (11)
(13) the future event E11 of negative nature may occur
premiss
(14) ∴ the future event E11 of negative nature will occur
from (11), (13)
The essence of such reasoning is of a logically inductive nature. The patient enumerates then some events of his/her past or present life, the nature of which he/she considers as negative. He/she reaches then by generalisation the conclusion according to which all events that which occur to him/her are negative. From this generalisation, he/she infers a prediction relating to a future event, likely to happen, which he/she considers as negative. The patient is thus led to the anxiogenous conclusion that an event of negative nature is going to occur.
In such reasoning, it is worth pointing out that the reference class identifies itself with the class of past, present and future events, of the patient’s life. Typically, in this type of reasoning, the generalisation is grounded on present or past events, while a future event is the object of the corresponding inductive prediction. This is different from the reference class applicable to the cognitive distortions mentioned above, where the reference class identifies itself exclusively with the future events of the patient’s life.
At this stage, it proves to be necessary to identify the fallacious steps in the patient’s reasoning, to allow their use in cognitive therapy of GAD. To this end, we can differentiate several steps in the structure of the corresponding reasoning. It proves indeed that some steps are valid arguments (an argument is valid when its conclusion is true if its premises are true), while others are invalid. For this purpose, it is worth drawing within this type of reasoning, a distinction between primary, secondary or ternary anxiogenous arguments.
Primary anxiogenous arguments
The first step in the type of aforementioned reasoning, consists for the patient to think to a past negative event, in the following way:
(1) the event E1 of negative nature did occur to me
It is however possible to describe more accurately the corresponding cognitive process, under the form of an argument that we can term a primary anxiogenous argument, the structure of which is the following:
(1a) the event E1 did occur to me
(1b) the event E1 was of negative nature
(1) ∴ the event E1 of negative nature did occur to me
from (1a), (1b)
By such cognitive process, the patient is led to the conclusion that some negative event did occur to him/her. This type of argument proves to be entirely valid inasmuch as the event in question presents well, objectively, a negative nature. However, it can also turn out to be invalid, if the event in question presents, objectively, a positive (or neutral) nature. What is then defective in this type of reasoning, is the fact that premise (1b) turns then out to be false. Such can notably be the case for example if the patient makes use of a cognitive distortion such as requalification in the negative. In such case, the patient considers then as negative an event the nature of which is objectively positive.
Secondary anxiogenous arguments
Anxiogenous secondary arguments are constituted, at the level of the above-mentioned reasoning, of the part that takes into account the instances (1)-(10) and proceeds then by generalisation. The patient counts thus some instances of events that did occur to him/her, the nature of which he/she considers as negative, and concludes that all events that did occur to him/her were negative, in the following way:
(1) the event E1 of negative nature did occur to me
(2) the event E2 of negative nature did occur to me
(…)
(10) the event E10 of negative nature did occur to me
(11) ∴all events that occur to me are of negative nature
from (1)-(10)
Such generalisation may constitute a fully valid argument. For the resulting generalisation constitutes a fully correct inductive reasoning, if the premises (1)-(10) are true. However, such type of reasoning is most often defective from two different viewpoints, thus distorting the conclusion which results from it. Above all, as we have did just see it, some past events of positive nature can have been counted among the number of negative events, by the effect of a requalification in the negative. In that case, the enumeration of instances includes then some false premises, thus invalidating the resulting generalisation. Secondly, some past or present positive (or neutral) events can have been omitted in the corresponding enumeration. Such omission can result from the use of some cognitive distortions, such as disqualification of the positive. In such case, the relevant class of reference consisting in present and past events of the patient’s life is only taken into account in a partial or erroneous way. The corresponding reasoning remains then logically valid, but proves to be incorrect, since it takes into account only partly the relevant instances within the reference class, that of the present and past events of the patient’s life.
As we see it finally, the patient proceeds then to a reconstruction of the relevant reference class which proves to be erroneous, due to the use of the following specific cognitive distortions: requalification in the negative and disqualification of the positive (and possibly, omission of the neutral). The corresponding type of reasoning is illustrated on the figure below:
A series of events of the patient’s life, seen (objectively) from the optimal system of taxa
After omission of the neutral
After requalification in the negative
After disqualification of the positive Conclusion: «All events that occur to me are negative »
Incorrect construction of the reference class for induction, after omission of the neutral, requalification in the negative, and then disqualification of the positive
Such mechanism, as we did see it, illustrates how the formation of anxious ideas is made. However; a mechanism of the same nature is also likely to contribute to their maintenance. For once the generalisation (11) according to which all events which occur to the patient are of negative nature, has been established by means of the above reasoning, its maintenance is made as soon as an event occurs which confirms this latter generalisation. When a new negative event indeed happens, the patient concludes from it that it confirms generalisation (11). Such mechanism, at the stage of the maintenance of anxious ideas, constitutes a confirmation bias. For the patient only counts those events of negative nature related to him/her that confirm indeed the generalisation (11), but without taking into account those events of positive nature which occur to him/her and that would then disconfirm the idea according to which all events which occur to him/her are of negative nature.
Ternary anxiogenous arguments
Lastly, it is worth mentioning the role played by ternary anxiogenous arguments which consist, at the level of the aforementioned reasoning, in the following sequence:
(11) ∴all events that occur to me are of negative nature
(12) ∴« I am always unlucky », « I am ill-fated »
It consists here of an argument which follows the conclusion of the secondary anxiogenous argument (11), and which, by an additional step (12), aims at interpreting it, at making sense of it. The patient interprets here the fact that the events which occur to him/her are negative, due to the fact that he/she is unlucky, ill-fated.
As we did see it, the interest of drawing a distinction between three types of arguments resides in the fact that each of them has a specific function: the primary stage proceeds by enumerating the instances, the secondary stage operates by generalisation, and the ternary stage, lastly, proceeds by interpretation (Franceschi 2008).
The present study, as we see it, extends recent work (Butler and Mathews on 1987, Dalgleish et al. 1997) emphasising the role played, in GAD, by anticipations concerning indeterminate situations related to future events. In this context, the specific cognitive distortions as well as a reasoning of an inductive structure, contribute then to the vicious circle (Sgard et al. 2006), which results from the process of formation and maintenance of the anxious state.
References
Butler G & Matews A. Cognitive processes in anxiety. Advances in Behaviour Research andTherapy 1983 ; 5 : 51-62.
Butler G & Matews A. Anticipatory anxiety and risk perception. Cognitive Therapy and Research 1987 ; 11 : 551-565.
Carleton R, Norton M & Aslundson G. Fearing the unknown: A short version of the Intolerance of Uncertainty Scale. Journal of Anxiety Disorders 2007 ; 21-1 : 105-117.
Canterbury R, Golden A, Taghavi R, Neshat-Doost H, Moradi A & Yule W. Anxiety and judgements about emotional events in children and adolescents. Personality and Individual Differences 2004 ; 36 : 695-704.
Dalgleish T, Taghavi R, Neshat-Doost H, Moradi A, Yule W & Canterbury R. Information processing in clinically depressed and anxious children and adolescents. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 1997 ; 38 : 535-541.
Dugas M, Buhr K & Ladouceur R. The role of intolerance of uncertainty in etiology and maintenance. In R. Heimberg, C. Turk, & D. Mennin (Eds.). Generalized anxiety disorder: Advances in research and practice. Guilford, New York, 2004(143-163).
Franceschi P. Compléments pour une théorie des distorsions cognitives. Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive 2007 ; 17-2 : 84-88. English translation.
Franceschi P. Une défense logique du modèle de Maher pour les délires polythématiques. Philosophiques 2008 ; 35-2 : 451-475. English translation.
Sgard F, Rusinek S, Hautekeete M & Graziani P. Biais anxieux de perception des risques. Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive 2006 ; 16-1 : 12-15.
The purpose of this study is to describe a conceptual framework for cognitive distortions, which notably allows to specify more accurately their intrinsic relationships. This conceptual framework aims at inserting itself within the apparatus of cognitive therapy and of critical thinking. The present analysis is based on the following fundamental concepts: the reference class, the duality and the system of taxa. With the help of these three notions, each cognitive distortion can be defined. A distinction is also made between, on the one hand, general cognitive distortions and on the other hand, specific cognitive distortions. The present model allows then to define within the same conceptual framework the general cognitive distortions such as dichotomous reasoning, disqualifying a given pole, minimisation and maximisation. It also allows to describe as specific cognitive distortions: disqualifying the positive, selective abstraction and catastrophism. Furthermore, the present model predicts the existence of two other general cognitive distortions: the omission of the neutral and requalifying in the other pole.
This paper is cited in:
Paul Franceschi, Théorie des distorsions cognitives : application à l’anxiété généralisée, Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, Volume 18, Issue 4, December 2008, Pages 127-131, English translation
Paul Franceschi, Théorie des distorsions cognitives : la sur-généralisation et l’étiquetage, Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, Volume 19, Issue 4, December 2009, Pages 136-140, English translation
Pramod Pandey, On the Nature of Reason in the present-day research, in Hasnain, Imtiaz, S. and Chaudhary, S. C. (eds.), Problematizing Language Studies: Cultural, Theoretical and Applied Perspectives- Essays in Honour of of Rama Kant Agnihotri. New Delhi: Aakar Books. Pp. 387-97, 2010.
Paul Franceschi, Traitement cognitif différentiel des délires oolythématiques et du trouble anxieux généralisé, Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, Volume 21, Issue 4, November 2011, Pages 121-125, English translation
Lisa Wake, Karl Nielsen, Nandana Nielsen & Catalin Zaharia, Depression symptom clusters, in “The Clinical Effectiveness of Neurolinguistic Programming”, Routledge 2013, edited by Lisa Wake, Richard M. Gray and Frank S. Bourke
Lizet Fernandez-Jammet, Evaluation longitudinale de l’efficacité d’une prise en charge cognitivo-comportementale de groupe destinée à des patients atteints de fibromyalgie, dissertation doctorale, 2016
Hélène Richard-Lepouriel, Trouble bipolaire, auto-stigmatisation et restructuration cognitive : une première tentative de prise en charge, Journal de Thérapie Comportementale et Cognitive, Volume 27-4, November 2017, Pages 177-183
Valérie Pennequin & Nicolas Combalbert, L’influence des biais cognitifs sur l’anxiété chez des adultes non cliniques, Annales Médico-psychologiques, Volume 175, Issue 2, February 2017, Pages 103-107
Anita Robert, Nicolas Combalbert, Valérie Pennequin, Etude des profils de distorsion cognitive en fonction des états anxieux et dépressifs chez des adultes tout-venant, Annales Médico-Psychologiques 176 (2018) 225–230
Nawal Ouhmad, Nicolas Combalbert, Wissam El-Hage, Cognitive distortions and emotion regulation among post traumatic stress disorder victims, in Psychological Applications and Trends, Ed. by C. Pracana & M. Wang, InScience Press, 2019
Paul Franceschi, For a Typology of Auditory Verbal Hallucinations Based on their Content, Activitas Nervosa Superior, volume 62, pages 104–109, 2020
A.Robert, N.Combalbert, V.Pennequin, R.Deperrois, N.Ouhmad, Création de l’Échelle de Distorsions Cognitives pour adultes (EDC-A) : étude des propriétés psychométriques en population générale et association avec l’anxiété et la dépression, Psychologie Française, 2021
Deperrois Romain & Nicolas Combalbert, Links between cognitive distortions and cognitive emotion regulation strategies in non-clinical young adulthood, in Psychological Applications and Trends, Ed. by C. Pracana & M. Wang, InScience Press, 2021
Ouhmad, Nawal & El-Hage, Wissam & Combalbert, Nicolas. (2022), Maladaptive cognitions and emotional regulation in PTSD, 3-7, Conference: International Psychological Applications Conference and Trend, doi:10.36315/2022.
Complements to a Theory of Cognitive Distortions
Paul FRANCESCHI
The cognitive distortions, introduced by Aaron Beck (1963, 1964) and Albert Ellis (1962) are traditionally defined as fallacious reasoning that plays a crucial role in the emergence of certain mental disorders. The cognitive therapy in particular is based on the identification of these cognitive distortions within the everyday way of thinking of the patient, and their replacement by alternative reasoning. Traditionally, the cognitive distortions are represented as one of the twelve following irrational modes of reasoning: 1. Emotional reasoning 2. Overgeneralization 3. Jumping to conclusions (or arbitrary inference) 4. Dichotomous reasoning 5. Should statements (Ellis 1962) 6. Fortune telling or mind reading 7. Selective abstraction 8. Disqualifying the positive 9. Maximisation and minimisation 10. Catastrophism 11. Personalisation 12. Labelling.
Under their classical form which is that of an enumeration, the cognitive distortions plays a central role within the field of cognitive therapy. Considering also their widespread nature in normal reasoning, one can think however that an accurate understanding of the cognitive distortions proves also to be useful outside the field of psychopathology. In particular, the cognitive distortions can also be seen as part of the apparatus which constitutes critical thinking. For these reasons, it appears that a conceptual framework, notably allowing to define the relationships between the different cognitive distortions, could also turn out to be useful. In what follows, we shall set out to present a general theory of the cognitive distortions, which brings a certain number of supplementary elements in comparison with classical theory.
1. Main notions
The present framework allows to represent several classical cognitive distortions: dichotomous reasoning, disqualification of one of the poles, selective abstraction, minimisation and maximisation. To these, one can add two other cognitive distortions of which the present model allows to predict the existence and which are closely related to the classical cognitive distortions, although they do not appear, to the knowledge of the author, to the number of these last. It consists of the omission of the neutral and the requalification in the other pole.
The cognitive distortions can be constructed, in the present model, from three main notions: the reference class,the duality and the system of taxa. It is necessary, in a preliminary way, to set out to describe these three notions. The reference class, above all, is constituted by a group of phenomena or objects. Several examples can be given here: the class composed of the events and facts of the patient’s life; the class of the future events of the patient’s life; the class constituted by all the parts of the patient’s body; the class which is made up of the patient’s character’s traits.
The notion of duality, second, corresponds to a pair of concepts such as Positive/Negative, Internal/External, Collective/Individual, Nice/Ugly, etc. A duality corresponds then to a criterion under the angle of which the elements of the reference class can be considered or evaluated. Let us denote by A/Ā a given duality, where A and Ā constitute then dual concepts. An enumeration (necessarily partial) of the dualities is as follows: Positive/Negative, Internal/External, Quantitative/Qualitative, Visible/Invisible, Analytical/synthetic, Absolute/Relative, Abstract/Concrete, Static/Dynamic, Unique/Multiple, Aesthetics/Practice, Definite/Vague, Finite/Infinite, Simple/Composite, Individual/Collective, Implicit/Explicit, Intentional/Unintentional.
Finally, thepatient’s system of taxa consists of a taxonomy which allows the patient to evaluate and to classify the elements of the reference class, according to the criterion corresponding to a given duality A/Ā. These taxa can be considered as “what can see” the patient. It consists of a system of values that is inherent to the patient or of a filter through which the patient “sees” the elements of the reference class, i.e. the phenomena or the objects of reality. The figure below represents an optimal system of taxa.
Fig.1. The optimal system of taxa
This last is composed of 11 spheres which represent each a given taxon. The system of taxa is optimal, because all taxa are present. On the other hand, if the patient does not have some taxa, he cannot see nor count the corresponding elements. For example, if he/she lacks the taxa of the duality A/Ā corresponding to pole A, he cannot see the corresponding elements. In the same way, if the patient has no neutral taxon in his/her system of taxa, he cannot see the neutral elements of the reference class. More formally, let us consider then a series of n elements E1, E2, …, En such that each of them has, in a objective way, a degree d[Ei] in a duality A/Ā comprised between -1 and 1 (d Î [-1, +1]). We can consider then a series including 11 elements, E1, E2, …, E11, which present an objective increasing degree (the choice of 11 elements is here arbitrary, and any other number would also do the job). Let us pose then: d[E1] = -1, d[E2] = -4/5, d[E3] = -3/5, d[E4] = -2/5, d[E5] = -1/5, d[E6] = 0, d[E7] = 1/5, d[E8] = 2/5, d[E9] = 3/5, d[E10] = 4/5, d[E11] = 1. Let us also define a subjective degree D[Ei] such that it is attributed by the patient to each of the Ei. So, E1-E5 corresponds to the pole A of duality A/Ā, E6 to the neutral taxon and E7-E11 corresponds to the pole Ā. Moreover, this optimal system of taxa can be assimilated with one Likert scale with 11 degrees.
At this stage, we are in a position to define the main cognitive distortions, and it is worth considering them in turn. The cognitive distortions can be defined as a type of reasoning which leads to favour, without objective grounds, a subset of the taxa applicable to a given duality A/Ā, in order to qualify a given reference class. It also proves to be useful to draw a distinction, in a preliminary way, between the general cognitive distortions and the specific cognitive distortions. The general cognitive distortions relate to all reference classes and all dualities. By contrast, the specific cognitive distortions are mere instances of the general cognitive distortions which are inherent to a given reference class and to a given duality.
2. The cognitive distortions
2.1 Dichotomous reasoning
In the present context, dichotomous reasoning (or all-or-nothing thinking) can be defined as a general cognitive distortion which leads the patient to consider a given reference class only according to the two extreme taxa which relate to every pole of a given duality. With this type of reasoning, the patient ignores completely the presence of degrees or of intermediate steps. In his/her taxa system, the patient has as well the two extreme taxa corresponding to poles A and Ā. The defect in that way of considering things is that facts or objects corresponding to intermediary taxa are not taken into account. So it results from it a reasoning without nuances nor gradation, which proves to be maladapted to properly apprehend the diversity of human situations. Formally, dichotomous reasoning consists in taking into account only the elements of the reference class such as|d[Ei]| = 1, ord[E1] = 1 ord[E11] = -1, by ignoring all the others.
Fig. 2. Dichotomous reasoning
2.2 The disqualification of one of the poles
In the present model, the disqualification of one of the poles is the general cognitive distortion which leads to grant an arbitrary priority in one of the poles of a given duality, in order to qualify the elements of a reference class. It consists then in the fact of attributing more importance to one of the poles rather than to the other one, in the lack of objective motivation. The taxa corresponding to one of the poles of a given duality are lacking in the patient’s system of taxa. So, the patient sees things only through the prism of pole A (respectively Ā), by ignoring completely the viewpoint of the opposed pole Ā (respectively A). Formally, the disqualification of one of the poles leads to consider only the Ei such that d[Ei] ≤ (respectivelyd[Ei] ≥ 0), by ignoring any events such thatd[Ei] > 0 (respectivelyd[Ei] < 0).
Fig. 3. The disqualification of one of the poles
An instance of the disqualification of one of the poles consists in the disqualification of the positive. This last can be analysed, in the present context, as a specific instance of the disqualification of one of the poles, which applies to the Positive/Negative duality and to the reference class including the facts and events of the patient’s life. The patient tends then to ignore positive events, by considering that they do not count, for any reason. Such instance finds to apply in the cognitive therapy of depression.
Another instance of the disqualification of one of the poles also applies to the Positive/Negative duality and to the reference class which comprises the character’s traits of the patient. This one completely ignores his/her positive character’s traits (qualities) and only directs his/her attention to his/her negative character’s traits (defects). This encourages then him/her to conclude that he/she “is worth nothing”, that he/she is “a failure”. Such instance also applies in the cognitive therapy of depression.
2.3 Arbitrary focusing on a given modality
Another type of cognitive general distortion consists in arbitrary focusing on a modality of a given duality. In the present context, this type of general cognitive distortion leads to favour one taxon in the patient’s system of taxa, by ignoring all the others. In arbitrary focusing, the taxon being discussed is present in the patient’s system of taxa, and is affected to an unique element of the reference class. There is eclipsing (in general temporary) of others taxa and other elements of the reference class, so that the patient is haunted by this specific element.
Fig. 4. Arbitrary focusing
A particular instance of this type of general cognitive distortion, relates to the reference class of the facts of the patient’s life, and to the Positive/Negative duality. It is a specific cognitive distortion, which consists in focusing on a negative event of the patient’s life. It is then one of the classical cognitive distortions, defined as selective abstraction (Mental filter), which consists in the fact of choosing one detail with a negative connotation and to focalise on it. Suchlike, the patient sees only this detail, and his/her vision{view} of reality is darkened because it is entirely tinted with this particular event. Such instance applies in the cognitive therapy of depression.
One can also mention another instance of arbitrary focusing, which also applies to the Positive/Negative duality, but relates to the class of reference composed of the hypothetical future events of the patient’s life. In that case, the patient focalises on the possible happening of a very negative event. Such instance finds to apply in the cognitive therapy of generalised anxiety disorder.
Another specific instance of arbitrary focusing applies to the Nice/Ugly duality and to a reference class which identifies itself with all the parts of the patient’s body. The patient focalises then on a detail of his/her anatomy which he considers to be ugliness. The patient has well, in his/her system of taxa the Ugly taxon in question. Moreover, he/she affects this taxon to an unique part of his/her body, while all the others taxa are temporarily eclipsed. Such specific cognitive distortion finds to apply in the cognitive therapy of body dysmorphic disorder (Neziroglu and Yaryura-Tobias 1993, Veale and Riley 2001, Veale 2004).
2.4 The omission of the neutral
The present model also leads to predict the existence of another type of general cognitive distortion, which consists in the omission of the neutral. This latter cognitive distortion results from the absence, in the patient’s system of taxa, of the neutral taxon. It follows that the elements of the reference class which can objectively be defined as neutral with regard to a given duality A/Ā, are not taken into account by the patient. Formally, the patient omits to consider the Ei such that d[Ei] = 0. The omission of the neutral sometimes plays an important role, notably when there is a gaussian distribution of the elements of the reference class, where the elements objectively corresponding to the neutral taxon are precisely those which are the most numerous.
Fig. 5. The omission of the neutral
2.5 The requalification in the other pole
The present model also leads to predict the existence of another type of general cognitive distortion. That is the reasoning which consists in re-qualifying an event belonging to a given duality A, in the other duality Ā. Formally, the subjective degree attributed by the patient to a given event E is the opposite of its objective degree, so that: D[E] = (-1) x d[E].
Fig. 6. The requalification into the other pole
A characteristic instance of requalification in the other pole consists in the specific cognitive distortion which applies to the class of the events of the patient’s life and to the Positive/Negative duality. This consists typically in re-describing as negative an event which should be objectively considered as positive. By requalifying positive events in a negative way, the patient can reach the conclusion that all events of his/her life are of a negative nature. For instance, by considering the past events of his/her life, the patient notes that he/she made no act of violence. He/she considers this to be “suspect”. This type of instance also finds to apply within the cognitive therapy of depression.
Another instance of requalification in the other pole consists in the specific cognitive distortion which applies to the class of the parts of the patient’s body and to the Nice/Ugly duality. Typically, the patient re-qualifies as “ugly” a part of his/her body which is objectively “nice”. Such specific cognitive distortion relates to the cognitive therapy of body dysmorphic disorder.
2.6 Minimisation and maximisation
This general cognitive distortion consists in attributing to an element of the reference class, a taxon according to the criterion of a duality A/Ā which proves to be lower (minimisation) or greater (maximisation) than its objective value. It consists here of a classical cognitive distortion. The subjective degree D[E] which is attributed by the patient to an event E differs significantly from its objective degree d[E]. In minimisation, this subjective degree is distinctly less than, so that |D[E]| < |d[E]|. In maximisation, by contrast, the subjective degree is distinctly greater, such that |D[E]| > |d[E]|.
Fig. 7. Maximisation and minimisation
A specific instance of minimisation relates to the class of the facts of the patient’s life and to the Positive/Negative duality. The patient tends to consider certain facts of his/her existence as less positive than they in reality are. In maximisation, he/she considers certain facts of his/her life as more negative than they really are. In the present context, the classical cognitive distortion of catastrophism (or dramatisation) can be considered as a specific cognitive distortion, which consists of a maximisation applied to the negative pole of the Positive/Negative duality. The patient attributes then a subjective degree D[E] in the Positive/Negative duality to an event, while the absolute value of its objective degree d[E] is very distinctly lesser. Such instance applies to the cognitive therapy of depression.
3. Conclusion
As we see it, the present theory provides several elements, in comparison with classical theory, that allow to define and to classify the classical cognitive distortions, within the same conceptual framework. These last are considered, either as general cognitive distortions, or as specific cognitive distortions, i.e. as instances of the general cognitive distortions which relate to a given reference class and duality. Thus, dichotomous reasoning, maximisation and minimisation constitute general cognitive distortions. In addition, disqualification of the positive, selective abstraction, selective negative focus and catastrophism constitute then specific cognitive distortions. Besides, the present analysis allowed to describe two additional general cognitive distortions: the omission of the neutral and the requalification in the other pole.
References
Beck AT.: 1963, Thinking and depression: Idiosyncratic content and cognitive distortions. Archives of General Psychiatry9, 324-333.
Beck AT.: 1964, Thinking and depression: Theory and therapy, Archives of General Psychiatry10, 561-571.
Ellis A.: 1962, Reason and Emotion in Psychotherapy, Lyle Stuart, New York.
Neziroglu FA et JA. Yaryura-Tobias: 1993, Exposure, response prevention, and cognitive therapy in the treatment of body dysmorphic disorder. Behav Ther 24, 431-438.
Veale D et S. Riley: 2001, Mirror, mirror on the wall, who is the ugliest of them all? The psychopathology of mirror gazing in previous termbody dysmorphic disorder.next term. Behaviour Research and Therapy39, 1381-1393.
Veale D.: 2004, Advances in a cognitive behavioural model of body dysmorphic disorder. Body Image1, 113-125.
A paper published in Activitas nervosa Superior (2020), 62, pages 104–109.
Auditory verbal hallucinations (AVHs) are a common symptom of schizophrenia. Studies have focused on a classification of AVHs, based on different criteria. Subtypes of AVHs have been defined, distinguishing according to whether they are internal/external, single/multiple, unimodal/multimodal, benevolent/malevolent, permanent/intermittent, etc. The purpose of this study is to propose a classification of AVHs based on their content. We first identify the subtype that is directly associated with the polythematic delusions inherent in schizophrenia. Second, we distinguish subtypes related to other comorbid psychiatric disorders associated with schizophrenia in the patient: generalized anxiety disorder, depression, body dysmorphic disorder, etc. Finally, we suggest that such a differentiation could allow a correlative adaptation of the corresponding cognitive-behaviour therapy.
This paper is cited in:
Isaacson, Maria et al. “The cognitive-phenomenological assessment of delusions and hallucinations at the early intervention in psychosis service stage: The results of a quality improvement project.” Early intervention in psychiatry (2022)